An Exploration of the Conceptual
Foundations of Western Herbalism and Biomedicine
With Reference to Research
Design
Matthew Wood Registered Herbalist (AHG)
6001 Sunnyfield Road,
Minnetrista, Mn. 55364
Master of Science Degree (Herbal Medicine)
Submitted: January 2006
Scottish School
of Herbal Medicine
University of Wales
[This edition has been slightly corrected due to feedback from my
committee.]
This report is submitted in fulfillment of the
requirements of the Scottish School of Herbal Medicine and the University of Wales for the award of MSc (Hons.) in Herbal
Medicine.
Abstract
Western herbalism – the practice of herbal medicine in modern,
English-speaking areas – is in a period of change, when many new and old
concepts are in competition for recognition. Biomedicine has proposed a strict
interpretation of herbal research, in which the experience, tradition, and
conceptual framework of Western herbalism is substantially ignored in favor of
the biomedical ‘gold standards:’ double blind clinical trials and
pharmacological studies. In this paper the author proposes that biomedical
research methods are not the only appropriate method for the study of
herbalism. Instead, Western herbalism, to be a scientific field in its own
right, needs to develop its own conceptual foundation and from this its own
methods of research. Towards this end the author examines questions of
science, paradigms, holism, biomedicine, research, and knowledge-gathering in
traditional herbalism and biomedical research design. This includes visionary
and intuitive methods that have not included in conventional scientific work.
The paper concludes that established methods of research in herbalism,
biomedical models for research, and visionary and intuitive approaches can all
contribute to a healthy herbal science. It also suggests that visionary and
intuitive methods can improve the holistic element in Western herbalism. It
suggests that a ‘confluence’ of results from different approaches may produce
more certainty in herbal knowledge than strict adherence to a single or few
methods. Of special interest is the unlooked for conclusion that ‘case series’
study should be developed to provide research that can benefit Western
herbalism and improve its scientific foundation.
List of Contents
1. Introduction
2. Review and Analysis
3. Methods
4. Modern Western Herbalism
5. Paradigms and the Study of Science
6. Paradigms and Biomedicine
7. Paradigms and Holistic Medicine
7.1. The Goodness of Nature
7.2. Self Healing
7.3. Spirituality
7.4. Vitalism
7.5. The Individual
7.6. Holism
7.7. Energetics
8. Paradigms and Herbalism
8.1. Empirical Science
8.1.1. Empirical
Research: Taste
8.1.2. Empirical
Research: Animal Use
8.1.3. Empirical
Research: Case Histories
8.2. Rational Science
8.2.1. Research on Theory
8.3. Experimental Science
8.3.1. Pharmacological
Research
8.3.2. Clinical Trials
and Herbal Medicine
8.4. Visionary Science
8.4.1. Visionary Research
8.5. Analogical Science
8.5.1. Analogical
Research
8.6. Authoritarian Science
8.6.1. Biomedical
Research and Herbal Tradition
9. Discussion
10. Conclusions
11. References
Acknowledgments
The author gratefully acknowledges the help of
Clara NiiSka, MSc. (liberal studies), University of Minnesota, for her
assistance in reading and criticizing the manuscript, Robert Schmidt, of
Project Hindsight, in Cumberland, Maryland, a professional Greek translator and
scholar of Greek science, for his insights in Greek science and ‘archealogical
science,’ Frank H. Wood, professor emeritus of educational psychology,
University of Minnesota, for his contributions regarding research, Midge
Whitelegg, Ph.D., F.N.I.M.H., Department of Nursing, University of Central
Lancashire, who provided several important articles and helpful comments, and Clair
Teegarden, of Minnetonka, Minnesota, who provided assistance with Internet
research.
1. Introduction
Extensive public use of complementary and alternative medicine (CAM)
(Eisenberg, Davis, Ettner, Appel, Wilkey, Van Rompay, and Kessler, 1998),
sometimes also called holistic medicine, led to an examination of the movement
by governments in Britain and America. Scientific research into the phenomenon was
recommended (United Kingdom House of Lords Select Committee on Science and
Technology, 2000; United States Department of Health and Human Services,
2002).
Response to government initiatives
within the biomedical field has been diverse. Prominent American medical
journals have suggested that CAM be investigated using conventional biomedical
methods alone and that holistic professions be ignored and eliminated (Angell
and Kassirer, 1998; DeAngelis and Fontanerosa, 2003). This corresponds to past
experience in America, where holistic professions have been frequently
persecuted and banned (Milton, 1996). A more conciliatory attitude in found
in prominent British biomedical journals. Here the suggestion was made that
complementary and alternative disciplines should engage in research to
establish the reputation of their own professions (Haynes, 1999). These two
thoughts – the threat of external take over and elimination of holistic
professions, and the suggestion that holistic medicine increase its standing
through conducting its own research – have led to the publication of the
present paper.
Until the last two decades of the
twentieth century, Western herbalism maintained its own conceptions and methods
of research. These consisted primarily of empiricism (experience and
observation), theory based on experience, and tradition based on experience
(Crellin and Philpott, 1990).
Empiricism is considered a
fundamental part of biomedical education and practice (Sackett, Richardson,
Rosenberg, Haynes, 1997). Since empiricism is a fundamental tool of scientific
and medical research (Carr, 1992; Kosso, 1992, Fugh-Berman, 1996), these
methods cannot be considered unscientific. Yet, leading biomedical journals
have proposed that the study of holistic medicine and herbalism be founded
exclusively on biomedical research (pharmacology and randomized controlled
trials), without reference to experience, theory, or tradition within holistic
professions (Angell and Kassirer, 1998; DeAngelis and Fontanerosa, 2003;
Leibovici, 1999).
The biomedical approach has been
adopted by some herbalists and herbal writers (Mills and Bone, 2000). Others,
however, have attempted to enlarge Western herbalism by introducing methods
originating in traditional or subjective sources that include visionary and
intuitive practices rejected by modern science (Cown, 1995, Buehner, 1996).
Conflicting concepts of herbalism are apparent in the survey of contemporary
Western herbal literature cited in section 4, ‘Modern Western Herbalism.’
Hence, the author concluds that basic assumptions in herbalism are not settled
but subject to debate.
In order to discuss this debate
within Western herbalism it is helpful to understand the nature of scientific
change and debate at such periods. In 1962 Kuhn (1970) introduced the concept
of the paradigm to describe scientific concepts and their ability to change in
professional debate. The paradigm is a theory or assumption, or collection of
them, which defines a field. He differentiated between ‘normal science,’ which
proceeds from a concensus on theories and assumptions, and ‘scientific
revolution,’ when adherents of different theories or paradigms contend with
each other for recognition and dominance.
The present author, concluding above
that Western herbal medicine is in such a period, applies Kuhn’s (1970) model to
hebalism for two reasons. First, it may be beneficial for herbalists to
understand and define the nature of the debate they are in. Second, it may
facilitate discussion of specific theories, practices, and assumptions
currently being considered for inclusion in Western herbalism. It is to be
hoped that this application of the paradigmatic model will sharpen issues of
debate while diminishing the sharpness of feeling often associated with
professional debate.
The current paper attempts to provide
basic materials for study and selection among different competing ideas. It is
intended to support herbalists who want to be in charge of their own destiny by
developing a profession based on theories, traditions, conceptions, research,
and practices consciously examined, compared, and selected by themselves,
rather than by a competing profession imposing standards upon them. It also
attempts to define and reconcile so-called scientific and nonscientific
approaches to knowledge, so that herbalists can select from the greatest
possible diversity of methods, without having to limit their choices to narrow
or rigid standards.
2. Review and Analysis
The contemporary practice of Western
herbalism has not been widely studied in scientific research and literature.
Only one extensive treatment of the subject has been undertaken by
scientifically trained observers (Crellin and Philpott, 1990). They noted that
previous studies by folklorists, anthropologists, sociologists, and pharmacologists
focused on magical recipes and charms, the sociology of complementary and
alternative medicine, its impact on the community, and the possible utility of
traditional medicinal plants for modern pharmacology. By comparison, their
study focused on the actual practice of herbal medicine in America.
Crellin and Philpott (1990) used an
historical method to interpret Western herbalism. They adopted this approach
because of the close historical relationship between herbalism and conventional
medicine, and the diversity characteristic of herbal practitioners. This
allowed them to catalogue, trace, and compare different practices and ideas
within the field, and their relationship to conventional medicine. The initial
study was limited to a single individual, Tommie Bass, a rural practitioner
living in northwestern Georgia. They record his views, theories, experiences,
and practices, then compare them with the larger herbal and medical tradition.
Crellin and Philpott (1990) isolated
several important methods used to gather knowledge in traditional herbalism.
The most significant of these are empiricism, theory, and tradition.
“Empiricism – observation and information gathered
supposedly without theoretical presuppositions – is conspicuous in all areas of
medicine. . . [and is] prominent in many current herbal practices” (Crellin and
Philpott, 1990, 1:12).
“When the ‘rampant empiricism’ – as it is often called –
in medicine at any time is examined closely, it is often seen to be sustained
by theoretical or cultural notions” (Crellin and Philpott, 1990, 1:13).
“There is no doubt that theory has played a considerable
role in the enlargement of the materia medica over time within both domestic
and professional medicine” (Crellin and Philpott, 1990, 1:13).
The three theories most prominent in herbal medicine,
according to Crellin and Philpott (1990), are:
(1) humoralism,
(2) the relationship of taste to property,
and
(3) the doctrine of signatures.
The first theory classifies herbal
properties and disease symptoms into simple categories of excess or deficiency
of basic states or substances like:
(1) temperature (hot, cold),
(2) humidity (damp, dry),
(3) tension (constriction and relaxation),
and
(4) constituent (blood, phlegm, bile, etc.)
The second relates medicinal properties to:
(1) taste (bitter, sweet, salty, pungent,
acrid, sour) and,
(2) impression (stimulating, relaxing,
puckering or astringing, etc.)
The third relates:
(1) appearance,
(2) environmental niche, or
(3) physical properties of a plant
to its medicinal virtues (Crellin and Philpott,
1990).
Crellin and Philpott (1990) provide a
comprehensive view of herbal history, from early American colonization until
the late 1980s. The author found their observations in line with his own
knowledge of the field. However, vast changes occurred in CAM
in the decade following their examination, as biomedical and non-Western
standards and ideas exerted an influence on Western herbal medicine. This
situation is not even referred to by Crellin and Philpott (1990).
In order to describe the nature of
the change within herbalism, the author has provided a short literary survey,
characterizing herbal publications of the last two decades (section 4, ‘Modern
Western Herbalism,’ p. 7).
3. Methods
Although this is a paper on science, the historical methods of
Crellin and Philpott (1990) and Kuhn (1970) were selected to provide a context
within which to study different scientific options available for research in
Western herbal medicine. The subject has been so seldom examined by
conventional academicians, that it was thought necessary to consult Crellin and
Philpott (1990) to define past practices within the field. Thus, their input
is largely restricted to section 2, ‘Review and Analysis.’ The paradigmatic
method of Kuhn (1970), on the other hand, was adopted to classify and describe
different assumptions or guiding ideas in herbalism, science, and medicine.
Thus, it constitutes the prinicipal method used in this paper to discuss and
characterize information of use to herbalists.
The concept of the paradigm was
introduced by Kuhn (1970) to describe different suppositions and practices in
various fields of science, especially in disciplines undergoing profound
conceptual change. It was applied to modern holistic medicine almost from the
first announcement of its existence (Yahn, 1979). The following year one
researcher described seventeen distinct paradigms characteristic of holistic
medicine (Gordan, cited by Goldstein, 1999).
Kuhn (1970) recognized two different
usages of the term paradigm:
“On the one hand, it stands for the entire constellation
of beliefs, values, techniques, and so on shared by the members of a given community.
On the other, it denotes one sort of element in that constellation” (Kuhn,
1970, 175).
In this paper, ‘paradigm’ has been used in both
senses. In section 7, ‘Paradigms and Holistic Medicine,’ (p. 14), the first of
these two approaches is applied. It discusses major paradigms associated with
the holistic movement in both popular and scientific discussion. Thus, it
chronicles the ‘constellation’ of paradigms which characterizes holistic
medicine. Section 8, ‘Paradigms and Herbal Research,’ (p. 18), adheres to the
second definition. Here the attempt is made to arrive at the fundamental
‘elements’ from which such ‘constellations’ of belief and practice are
derived.
Several terms used in this paper
ought to be defined. English language herbalism is known to participants in
the field as “Western herbalism” (Hoffmann, 2003, 1), in distinction to Chinese
and Ayurvedic herbalism. This term has been adopted throughout this paper for
the sake of clarity. The following terms also need definition:
Western medicine: medicine as it was practiced in the West up to
the 1940s.
Biomedicine: modern medicine, no longer a ‘Western’ phenomenon.
Conventional medicine: both of the above.
Holistic medicine, unconventional medicine, and complementary and alternative medicine (CAM) are used interchangeably.
The author consulted his own library,
Hennepin County Library, and the University of Minnesota
Library for scientific and
historical information on Western herbalism, Western medicine, biomedicine, the
paradigmatic model, complementary and alternative medicine, and other subjects
related to this paper. Recent research and editorials on these subjects in the
most important English language professional medical journals were consulted to
determine the characteristic attitudes towards these subjects in contemporary
biomedical literature. Articles were located through research on the Internet
using ‘Google scholar’ and keywords including ‘medicine’ and ‘paradigm’ in
combination with ‘complementary,’ ‘alternative,’ and ‘holistic.’ The most often
cited articles were selected. Searches under specific subjects were also
pursued.
4. Modern Western Herbalism
The 1940s were a watershed for
Western herbalism. The use of whole plant parts in medicine was superseded by
the use of drugs made from isolated, synthesized molecules. The latter were
described as the ‘active ingredients’ of plants, implying that the rest of the
plant was inactive or less active. Herbal medicine was marginalized (Crellin
and Philpott, 1990). Widespread persecution of folk healers and unconventional
physicians was initiated in the United States including imprisonment and book
burning, physicians were not allowed to practice homeopathy or herbalism
without losing their licenses, and unlicensed practice by others was considered
illegal in all but a few states (Milton, 1996). The present author has also
argued that the practice of medicine itself changed, making it difficult for
younger herbalists to understand how to apply the materia medica they inherited
from the past (Wood, 2004). How did the profession deal with these changes?
A survey of contemporary herbal
literature shows that many authors imported concepts into Western herbalism
from other systems they deemed holistic. The Way of Herbs (Tierra,
1984) uses traditional Chinese medicine to classify Western herbs. The Yoga
of Herbs (Lad and Frawley, 1989) uses Ayurvedic principles from India.
The Traditional Healer (Chishti, 1989) follows the Greek/Arabic method.
The Wise Woman Herbal Healing Wise (Weed, 1989) claimed to reflect the
methods of traditional ‘wise women.’ Creating Your Herbal Profile (Hall,
1988) presented profiles of herbs resembling homeopathic constitutional
types.
During the late 1990s, as biomedical
interest in CAM and herbalism was on the increase, publications
appear written both by herbalists and biomedicists attempting to explain the
action of herbs according to biomedical standards. Publications reflecting
this perspective include Phytotherapy (Mills and Bone, 2000) and PDR
for Herbal Medicines (Fleming,
1998).
Herbal methodology based on early
twentieth century medicine did not completely disappear. One of the most
popular and influential texts of the past twenty five years has been The New
Holistic Herbal (Hoffmann, 1992). Here herbs are applied to body systems
(rather than specific lesions, as in modern biomedicine) and are classified by
‘action’ (astringent, bitter, demulcent, etc.) These methods are
characteristic of the medical and herbal approach of the early twentieth
century (Crellin and Philpott, 1990; Wood, 2004).
For many, the traditional method of
herbal practice explained by Hoffmann was as exotic as Chinese or Ayurvedic
medicine. In The Practice of Traditional Western Herbalism (Wood, 2004)
the present author attempted to explain early twentieth century medicine for
the modern herbal audience. He would point out that herbal education and
practice was legally irradicated in America from about 1950 to 1975, during the period of
persecution mentioned above (Milton, 1996), so that the traditional system of herbal
medicine was not readily understood by younger Americans. It was maintained in
isolated pockets, like Southern
Appalachia, where Tommie Bass
practiced (Crellin and Philpott, 1990). This may explain why all the above
books based on Chinese, Ayurvedic, Greek/Arabic, or ‘wisewoman’ herbalism are
written by Americans.
The above survey reveals polarities
in the herbal field between holism and biomedicine, tradition and innovation.
The author concludes that this diversity of opinion indicates that Western
herbalism is in the phase Kuhn (1970) called ‘scientific revolution,’ when the
supporters of different paradigms are in competition. The author suggests that
this circumstance recommends herbalists to the study of the concept of the
paradigm and its application within their field.
5. Paradigms and the Study of
Science
Kuhn (1970) explains that the
paradigm can be a law, theory, application of knowledge, or instrumentation –
or several of these together – that supports a certain perspective. Paradigms
can be theoretical or practical. Thus, the theory of general relativity
represented a change in paradigm from previous, Newtonian physics. In the same
fashion, the introduction of the microscope brought about a paradigmatic change
by allowing an entirely new view of the world. Together or individually,
paradigms
“provide models from which spring particular coherent
traditions of scientific research” (Kuhn, 1970, 10).
Such traditions are often named by
scientists and historians. Examples are Ptolemaic astronomy, Copernican
astronomy, Aristotelian, Newtonian, and Einsteinian physics, corpuscular
optics, and wave optics (Kuhn, 1970). Within Western herbalism the author
notes such named traditions as Greek or Galenic medicine, physio-medicalism,
and eclecticism.
When a paradigm has been accepted by
a group of scholars and a discipline is organized around it, practitioners
within the field no longer need to dispute fundamental assumptions. Work is
now directed by a recognized conceptual structure and generally recognized
definitions, resulting in a continuous development of interrelated
information. Problems are identified and solved within the established
paradigm. At this point the field usually generates its own societies,
journals, and claims for recognition in higher educational facilities. This
phase of activity Kuhn (1970, 35) calls “normal science.” The basic activity
of normal science is defined as “puzzle-solving” (Kuhn., 1970, 35).
When a paradigm does not adequately
explain study results or the nature of the world satisfactorily, alternate
paradigms are suggested and attract different adherents. This leads to
conflict within the field. During this period, ‘normal science’ is superseded
by the phase called ‘scientific revolution.’ This is a period of uncertainty
during which old paradigms are thrown into doubt and new ones generated (Kuhn, 1970).
When a new paradigm achieves
recognition in its field, replacing an old one, Kuhn called the change a
“paradigm shift” (Kuhn, 1970, 52). The introduction of cyber-technology in the
1990s is an example of a recent paradigm shift in science due to changes in
instrumentation; in biomedicine it led to a new approach or paradigm called
‘evidence-based medicine’ (EBM), discussed in section 8.3, ‘Experimental
Science,’ (p. 31).
During scientific revolution a field
is fraught with uncertainties and unanswered questions. However, as new
experience, research data, and instrumentation are acquired, guiding concepts
become clarified and competing explanations are eliminated until a single or
several complementary paradigms emerge which are able to adequately account for
the observed data. This arrival is, for a scientific community, a “sign of
maturity” (Kuhn, 1970, 11). A scientific culture that has reached this level
of agreement has more authority than one still developing basic concepts (Milton,
1996).
Kuhn (1970) was skeptical about the
objectivity of debate during periods of competition between different
paradigms.
“This issue of paradigm choice can never be
unequivocally settled by logic and experiment alone” (Kuhn, 1970, 94).
Paradigms are not derived from research; they
direct research. Therefore,
“A debate about paradigm choice. . . is necessarily
circular. Each group uses its own paradigm to argue in that paradigm’s
defense” (Kuhn, 1970, 94).
This position has been controversial.
Some critics take issue with the suggestion, as they perceive it, that science
is a mere belief system (Vickers, 1996; Horgan, 1997). But science has never
been based on certainty. It was always founded on theories, hypotheses,
probabilities, and now – as Kuhn (1970) has shown – assumptions. Instead of
rejecting the concept of the paradigm as a threat to the idea of objectivity in
science, a more mature view would see that it “sharpens the burden” on science
to
“allow for meaningful tests that genuinely put the
theory at risk” (Kosso, 1992, 133).
Another controversial point is Kuhn’s
(1970) argument that scientific models which have been cast aside in the
development of science are still as scientific today as they were when they
were accepted practice.
“Aristotle’s physics, understood on its own terms, was
simply different from, rather than inferior to, Newtonian physics” (Kuhn,
paraphrased by Horgan, 1997, 42).
Nor was Newton canceled out by Einstein:
“In so far as Newtonian theory was ever a truly
scientific theory supported by valid evidence, it still is” (Kuhn, 1970, 99).
Kosso (1992, 131) considered Kuhn’s
work to be “influential” and “high profile,” not only in historical discussion,
but in the design of scientific research. However, he recognized that it was
easy to misunderstand. The word ‘paradigm’ has entered into popular culture
and become widely used in nonscientific settings. Kuhn himself described it as
“hopelessly overused” and “out of control” (Kuhn, quoted by Horgan, 1997,
45).
6. Paradigms and Biomedicine
Most professional journals in
biomedicine have rejected discussion of CAM theories, concepts, and paradigms. They
advocate study of CAM products, practices, and therapies using the
biomedical perspective or paradigm alone. For example, in 1998 the editors of NEJM
expressed the following opinion:
“There cannot be two kinds of medicine – conventional
and alternative. There is only medicine that has been adequately tested and
medicine that has not, medicine that works and medicine that may or may not
work. Once a treatment has been tested rigorously, it no longer matters
whether it was considered alternative at the outset. If it is found to be
reasonably safe and effective, it will be accepted” (Angell and Kassirer, 1998,
339:841).
The Final Report of the White
House Commission on Complementary and Alternative Medicine Policy quotes
the above statement with approval, noting that
“many of the commissioners agree with the editors”
(United States Department of Health and Human Services, 2002, 6).
The editors of JAMA proposed
that dietary supplements (including herbs) should be tested according to the
biomedical model, regulated as drugs if they are shown to be biologically
active, and removed from the marketplace if not (DeAngelis and Fontanarosa,
2003).
Only the 6th Report of the
House of Lords Select Committee on Science and Technology (2000) does not
follow this line, but advocates both quantitative and qualitative studies of
complementary and alternative medicine.
Vickers (1996) developed arguments
against the use of paradigms in the study of conventional and unconventional
medicine. Some are general objections to Kuhn. Others refer to the debate
between CAM and biomedicine. However, writing at a later
date, Kollman and Vickers (1999), published a series of articles on
complementary and alternative medicine in the BMJ acknowledging the
existence of the paradigmatic argument.
In a subsequent article in the BMJ,
Leibovici (1999) addressed a problem raised by the introduction of CAM:
which therapies and methods should be subjected to biomedical testing and which
should not? He suggested that any therapy that did not fit the “deep model” of
science should be ignored (Leibovici, 1999, 319:1631). He does not define a
‘deep model,’ but the context suggests that it is the basic paradigm of modern
science, i.e., the rational, material world view in which phenomenon have objective
explanations. This contrasts with the paradigm he attributed to holistic
medicine:
“The deep model of alternative medicine is
anthropocentric magic. The explanations of the practitioners of alternative
medicine are giving our patients a set of magical rules to control the physical
world, rules that have the human as the fulcrum. They are saying that herbs
are beneficial and can do no harm, a substance that causes complaints similar
to those observed in a patient will cure them if diluted to an infinitesimal
concentration, ‘we will adjust your Qi force’; these are phenomena that work
only on the living human, and not on any other component of the physical world”
(Leibovici, 1999, 319:1631).
The author cannot detect a difference
between Leibovici’s (1999) ‘deep model’ and a ‘paradigm.’ It appears,
therefore, that Leibovici (1999) uses a paradigmatic argument to arrive at the
same methodology suggested by other biomedical authors: ignore the paradigm of
holistic medicine and investigate the contents based solely on a biomedical
model.
Leibovici (1999) does not enter into
debate about ‘deep models’ with those whose ‘deep model’ he challenges. The
same tendency is seen in the previous biomedical writers. They feel at liberty
to ignore the arguments of those they challenge. In the United Kingdom, practitioners of systems not in agreement with the ‘deep model’ of
science would still be able to practice, since the law protects unlicensed
practitioners, but in the United
States there are no such Federal
safeguards. In the past, adherents of systems medicine has chosen to ignore
have been outlawed (Milton, 1998). Clearly, this is the intent of the NEJM
and JAMA editorials, which completely ignore holistic professions and
beliefs.
Leibovici (1999) is followed by a
commentary written by one of the editors of the BMJ. In “A warning to
complementary medicine practitioners: get empirical or else,” Haynes (1999,
319:1633) threatens CAM practitioners with the prospect that their
methods and tools will be taken over by conventional physicians if they do not
do research themselves and develop their profession in the same manner
conventional medicine has done. Going a step further, Haynes recommends that CAM
practitioners throw ‘deep models’ out the window:
“Deep models are for snobs, oppressors, and
wishful thinkers. The flat earth, phlogiston, bleeding, cupping, oppression of
women, the Aryan Race – what are these but ‘deep theories’?” (Haynes, 1999,
319:1634).
This rather strong language carries
the implication, at least to the ear of the present author, that average people
cannot or should not think for themselves. Haynes seems to say that only
scientists have the right to have a ‘deep model’ and they and their model
should not be questioned by ordinary people, who will make mistakes of a
childish, naive, or catastrophic nature. The author is concerned that the
thinking nonscientist might conclude from such statements that scientists, by
attempting to limit discussion of their field, take on the role of ‘snobs,
oppressors, and wishful thinkers.’ On the other hand, Haynes is the only
author who actually suggests an outlet by which CAM practitioners can
develop a profession – research.
The present author feels it is
necessary to point out what he considers to be poor definition of several terms
in the articles by Leibovici (1999) and Haynes (1999). Both these authors show
a tendency to confuse empiricism and experimentation. Leibovici (1999,
319:1631) refers to the “epitome” of “empiricism” as the “randomized controlled
trial.” Haynes (1999, 319:1633) threatens alternative practitioners to “get
empirical,” then describes “empiricism” as experimental research. Like many
modern scientific authors, these two do not differentiate between empiricism
and experimentation, yet these are entirely different scientific methods.
Empiricism refers to observation and experience yielding unsorted data, while
experimentation refers to designed experiments yielding statistically
significant information (Carr, 1992; Kosso, 1992).
Advocates of complementary and
alternative medicine frequently argue that it is not possible to test their
approach by conventional standards because the reductionism inherent in the
biomedical model eliminates variables intrinsic to holistic practice
(Goldstein, 1999). This difficulty has also been recognized by biomedical
writers:
“Responses to [CAM] treatment are
unpredictable and individual, and treatment is usually not standardized.
Designing appropriate controls for some complementary therapies. . . is
difficult, as is blinding patients to treatment allocation. Allowing for the
role of the therapeutic relationship also creates problems” (Kollman and
Vickers, 1999, 319:903).
However, research models have been
developed that do take into account the important holistic paradigms so easily
removed by reductionism. An example of one will be given in subsection 8.3.2,
‘Clinical Trials and Herbal Medicine,’ (p. 33).
The author concludes that biomedical
research, to the extent it is directed by the methods advocated by authors and
editorialists in major American biomedical journals, is not attempting to
expand biomedical hegemony to include CAM products and methods while disempowering
competing professions and their paradigms. This is in line with established
legislation in the United States, which makes it illegal for both medical doctors
and lay people to practice herbalism and homeopathy in almost all states, but
protects the sale of the products (Milton, 1996). In Britain, on the other
hand, where such practices enjoy legal status, the editoral tone is slightly
more accomodating.
7. Paradigms and Holistic
Medicine
The paradigmatic discussion advocated
by holistic practitioners represents a response to problems perceived in
conventional biomedicine by practitioners and the public alike.
“Taken altogether, the core beliefs of
alternative medicine, regardless of their origins hundreds or thousands of
years ago in faraway cultures, provide a current ‘response’ to the well
founded, highly rational critiques of biomedicine” (Goldstein, 1999, 70).
Ignoring paradigmatic debate sidesteps widespread
criticism. If these paradigms were being advanced by cranks with no public
following they would be irrelevant, but complementary and alternative medicine
enjoys enormous popularity. A recent survey of US consumers indicated that
there were more visits (629 million) to CAM practitioners in 1997 than to primary care
physicians (386 million) (Eisenberg, et al., 1998).
About a half dozen prominent
paradigms are frequently cited, both by exponents and critics, as
characteristic of holistic medicine. Kaptchuk and Eisenberg (1998) mention
nature, vitalism, science, and spirituality. Kollman and Vickers (1999) list
holism, the self healing ability of the body, spirituality, and the treatment
of the individual. Goldstein (1999) mentions holism, the mind/body/spirit
model, health and illness on a continuum, the concept of ‘energy,’ and vitalism.
The present paper arbitrarily describes the following seven: the goodness of
nature, self healing, spirituality, vitalism, the individual, holism, and
energetics.
7.1. The Goodness of Nature
Differences in approach to nature
constitute paradigmatic choices. Belief in the innate goodness of nature is
almost universal in holistic medicine and has been marked as such by most
researchers and advocates (Goldstein, 1999). In Western herbalism plants are
generally looked upon as representatives of the innate goodness of nature.
This tradition goes back at least to Samuel Thomson, who popularized herbal
medicine in pioneer America in the early nineteenth century as an
alternative to toxic mineral medicines and bloodletting (Thomson, 1825a).
Different perspectives have been used
to explain the goodness of nature. Kloss, a Seventh Day Adventist, entitled
his famous herbal Back to Eden (1962), giving his argument a
Biblical dimension. Hoffmann (1992), appealing to a modern readership,
advances Lovelock’s ‘Gaia’ hypothesis: natural healing is part of a balanced
ecosystem.
7.2. Self Healing
The self healing ability of the
organism is recognized by both conventional and unconventional medicine. CAM
places a high regard on the constructive, health-maintaining and self-healing
capacity of the body. Disease is sometimes considered by CAM
practitioners to be the result of not living and eating in harmony with
nature. Even further, there is sometimes an emphasis on the positive aspects
of disease. Blessed by Illness (Mees, 1983), argued in favor of the
strengthening effects of childhood diseases well before this concept appeared
in conventional immunology. Homeopathy developed a positive view of disease
symptoms, which are looked upon as the healthy response of the sick organism.
In homeopathy, the remedy sometimes temporarily intensifies the symptoms in
order to strengthen the curative response of the organism and allow it to
triumph over the disease (Panos and Heimlich, 1980). In naturopathy, diet and
exercise are used to strengthen the organism to overcome disease (Lindlahr,
1919). Even death is treated as a natural outcome, as seen in the work of
Elizabeth Kubler-Ross (1974), at one time ‘alternative,’ but now incorporated
into the hospice movement in conventional medicine.
7.3. Spirituality
Goldstein (1999) emphasizes that
holistic medicine appeals to many people who feel they need to make decisions
contributing to their spiritual, as well as their physical, well-being. This may
draw them away from conventional medicine, which directs its effects mainly
towards the condition of the physical body. Materialism is a dominant
characteristic of modern science and medicine that differentiates it from
holistic movements.
“The positive role of spiritual or religious
beliefs in the histories of almost every major alternative approach is
difficult to deny” (Goldstein, 1999, 75).
7.4. Vitalism
Vitalism is the concept that the
living body is animated by a spiritual or nonmaterial agency that marks the
true difference between life and death. This is a characteristic belief of the
holistic health movement. Thus, traditional Chinese medicine calls the life
force in the body qi, while Ayurveda calls it prana, and
homeopathy calls it the dynamis or vital force (Kaptchuk and
Eisenberg, 1998).
Herbalism sometimes shares this
view. Samuel Thomson’s followers felt that conventional medication was
directed against the vital force, towards the suppression of the self-healing
capacity of the organism, which they felt herbs supported (Thurston, 1900).
However, another prominent group of botanical physicians in the nineteenth
century, the eclectics, were more empirically ruthless and eschewed theories in
general, including vitalism. Thus, their “vitalism,” if we may call it such,
was purely experiential. Life was not a concept, but an experience to be
achieved through examination of the living body, in health and disease
(Scudder, 1985a).
7.5. The Individual
Holistic medicine places more
emphasis on the individual than biomedicine. Each client is evaluated as
unique and each practitioner is accepted as a unique person with skills
differing from his or her peers. The subjective symptoms, attitude, problems,
self-evaluation, and conditions of the patient are given greater weight than in
biomedical case taking. Treatment strategy is usually designed individually,
on a case by case basis. For many clients this increased attention is a source
of comfort which might itself have curative or psychological value (Goldstein,
1999).
7.6. Holism
Holism could be considered the fundamental concept behind holistic
medicine, since it has been adopted by practitioners to distinguish themselves
from conventional medicine (Yahn, 1979). Holism studies the whole, while
conventional medicine studies the parts. The latter approach is called
reductionism. A medical textbook defines reductionism as
“the exploring of details, and the details of
details, until all the smallest bits of the structure, or the smallest parts of
the mechanism are exposed to scrutiny. . . . Instead of reaching for the whole
truth, the scientist examines small, defined, and clearly separable phenomena”
(Wyngaarden and Smith, 1985, 5).
In holistic medicine both the
organism and the disease are frequently looked upon as whole and complete
entities and analysis begins from this perspective, rather than from the parts
or details (Goldstein, 1999). The description of the whole nature of an entity
demands its own vocabulary. This has often been called ‘energetics’ in modern
holistic practice. Energetics is described below for those not familiar with
the concept.
7.7. Energetics
Many holistic disciplines not only
recognize life energy, qi, or vital force, but describe this force as creating
identifiable ‘energy patterns.’ Thus, the ‘energy’ of a person may be tight or
loose, or the disease may be hot or cold. This subject is called ‘energetics’
by many holistic practitioners. A title reflecting this concept is The
Energetics of Western Herbs by Peter Holmes (1997).
Virtually all major systems of
traditional medicine, including Greek, Ayurvedic, and Chinese use some system
of energetics. The four elements of Greek medicine, the four qualities of Aristotle,
yin and yang, and the five elements and three doshas of India
are examples of ‘energetic’ systems of description. Western medicine and
herbalism, as practiced in the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries,
utilized terms such as irritation, excitation, relaxation, constriction,
contraction, depression, etc., to describe general ‘tissue states’ or
pathological patterns in the organism (Scudder, 1985a; Thurston, 1900).
Because energetics are not used in
biomedicine, their importance in traditional and holistic practice is sometimes
missed. For instance, Crellin and Philpott (1990) describe the herbs used by
Tommie Bass but do not mention his diagnostic or pathological conceptions. I
asked his life-long friend and student, Darryl Patton, how Bass visualized
disease. He responded that his teacher used the characteristic diagnostic
system of southern Appalachian folk medicine based on the blood (‘bad blood,’
‘sweet blood,’ ‘high blood,’ ‘low blood,’ etc.) and other folk medical
considerations (Patton, 2006).
8. Paradigms
and Herbal Research
Vickers (1996) notes that
complementary and alternative authors frequently focus on paradigmatic
questions rather than research. He detected an inverse correlation between
discussion of paradigms and the production of useful research. The above
enumeration of complementary and alternative paradigms tends to confirm Vickers
(1996), for none of them address the issue of research or the way in which the
information that constitutes CAM has been derived from nature. By describing
major characteristics of holistic medicine they serve an important function,
but this does not directly contribute to research. However, this does not mean
that research cannot be based upon paradigmatic constructs. Founding research
which included the characteristic paradigms of holistic medicine would
represent a positive response to the challenge laid down by Haynes
(1999).
The above paradigms may be used as
starting points for holistic and herbal research. However, the author is of
the opinion that it is more important to first define basic kinds of
scientific research, before setting off on an examination of specific holistic
paradigms. For this, the paradigmatic model is also available.
Kuhn (1977) demonstrated that even
within a single scientific field different kinds of science could be
identified. He differentiated the mathematical (or rational) approach from the
experimental. He did not define them as paradigms, but they have been widely viewed
as such (Eamon, 1994). Empiricism has also been identified as a paradigm
(Ginzburg, cited by Eamon, 1994).
A pre-Kuhnian author listed a total
of five “methods and procedures” for constructing systems of knowledge:
“revelation, authority, reason, experience, and
experimentation” (Clagett, 1955, 4).
This tabulation adds two more methods for
gathering and organizing knowledge – revelation and authority. It would seem
reasonable also to apply the Kuhnian label ‘paradigm’ to these procedures.
The present author found it necessary
to separate revelation into two separate categories. The concept of
‘revelatory’ science was used by Festugiere (Eamon, 1994) to explain the
approach to knowledge associated with the Hermetic literature (c. third century
ACE). These documents are largely presented as revelations, mostly from the
god of knowledge, Hermes. The actual method of analysis used in the Hermetica
has, however, been characterized as “sympathies and antipathies”
(Eamon, 1994, 18). This method is not based on revelations from gods, visions,
or dreams, but is analytical (see section 8.5, ‘Analogical Science, p. 38).
The author suggests that it reflects an ‘analogical’ method. Hence, the
revelatory paradigm has been split, in this paper, into the visionary and
analogical approaches.
This gives a total of six primary
scientific methods, procedures, or paradigms:
empiricism, rationalism, experimentation, the visionary
and analogical methods, and authoritarianism.
This collection is not intended to be viewed as a
comprehensive and exhaustive typology of science, but as a practical model for
a qualitative study of medicine and herbalism.
8.1. Empirical Science
Observation and experience are recognized as essential methods of
knowledge-gathering in science and medicine (Carr, 1992; Kosso, 1992;
Fugh-Berman, 1996). The unsorted information brought together through
empiricism constitutes a ‘collection,’ rather than a ‘system.’ This has led to
debate about whether empiricism can be considered a science, i.e., a ‘system of
knowledge.’ Kuhn (1970) did not think it qualified:
“Though this sort of fact-collecting has been
essential to the origin of many significant sciences, anyone who examines, for
example, Pliny’s encyclopedic writings or the Baconian natural histories of the
seventeenth century will discover that it produces a morass” (Kuhn, 1970, 16).
However, more recent historians of science have
concluded that empiricism by itself does constitute a scientific paradigm
(Ginzburg, cited by Eamon, 1994). The question is rather technical and for the
purpose of this paper empiricism will be considered a scientific paradigm.
The Hippocratic physicians represent
a school of medicine largely founded upon empirical methods. Their writings on
epidemics and aphorisms are collections of unsorted observations and
experiences, such as Kuhn (1970) describes. Whether or not this material forms
a ‘morass,’ it educated physicians for more than two thousand years (Cumston,
1987).
Empiricism is derived from the Greek
word for experience. The development of this method was the standard for which
Hippocratic physicians strove:
“In the Hippocratic corpus, experience (peire)
is the mark of the man who knows. It is synonymous with competence, and
always carries a positive connotation” (Jouanna, 1999, 257).
Because of their empirical approach,
the Hippocratic physicians were attacked by contemporaries who did not consider
such efforts to be scientific. One Hippocratic treatise, Tradition in Medicine,
responded to this charge by arguing
“Medicine has for long possessed the qualities
necessary to make a science. These are original observations and a known
method” (Hippocrates, 1950, 13).
The ‘original observations’ pertain
to health, illness, and diet. They are enlarged by a ‘known method’ – what
would be called ‘trial and error’ experiment. Tradition in Medicine refers,
for example, to altering the amounts and kinds of food on the sick to
understand their effect (Hippocrates, 1950).
The treatise argues against any
standard that is not empirical:
“One aims at some criterion as to what
constitutes a correct diet, but there is no standard by reference to which
accuracy may be achieved; physical sensation is the only guide” (Hippocrates,
1950, 17).
It also argues against any standard not easily
understood by the general population:
“If anyone departs from what is popular
knowledge and does not make himself intelligible to his audience, he is not
being practical” (Hippocrates, 1950, 21).
The earliest comprehensive writers on
the properties of plant medicines, Dioscorides and Plinius (first century CE),
were largely empirical, though Ritter (1985) discovered a pharmacological order
in Dioscorides that was not noticed by his readers. At a latter date, various
theories for predicting the effects of herbs based on temperature (hot/cold),
humidity (damp/dry), taste, organ affinity, etc., were introduced, mostly by
Galen (third century CE). These will be discussed under the next subsection,
8.2, ‘Rational Science,’ (p. 27).
Empirical and rational methods were
sometimes maintained alongside each other. Moses Maimonides (twelfth century)
divided discussion of materia medica into two sections, one based on Galen’s
theories of medicinal activity (taste, quality, organ affinity, etc.), the
other on ‘specific’ indications derived from clinical experience (Rosner, 1989,
346). This dual classification was still used by Salmon (1710) in his English
Herbal.
Western herbalism in the nineteenth
and early twentieth centuries was largely the product of a combination of
empirical experience, traditional indications carried down from the ancient
literature of European medicine, and new theories, practices, and remedies
introduced from America (Webb, 1916). The two most influential schools
of the period were physio-medicalism, derived largely from the teachings of
Samuel Thomson, and eclecticism, of which the leading thinker was John Scudder
(Haller, 1997).
Scudder (1827-93) advocated a
doctrine of relatively pure empiricism. He says the use of medicines is based
largely on tradition and experience in all schools:
“In ordinary practice, whether it be Old School
or Eclectic, there is no principle or law of cure. Remedies are not given
because they are opposed to or agree with disease action, but simply because
they have previously been used with reputed good success. It is, in fact, pure
empiricism” (Scudder, 1985b, 23).
For Scudder, life is not a principle
or theory, but a condition to be observed with the senses. Likewise, disease
is not a name or concept, but a disturbed expression of life to be sensed by
the physician.
“The first lesson in pathology we want to learn
is, that disease is wrong life. The first lesson in diagnosis is, that
this wrong life finds a distinct and uniform expression in the outward
manifestations of life, cognizable by our senses. The first lesson in
therapeutics is. . . to know the relation between the drug and the. . .
disease expression” (Scudder, 1985b, 15-16).
Scudder’s whole system is based
almost entirely on experience. He describes symptoms of ‘wrong life’ rather
than disease names, in a graphic manner that he anticipates will resonate with
the experiences of his readers:
“What is the color of health, as shown from the
blood? It is rosy, a light shade of carmine and lake, and is clear,
transparent, and offers no darkness, or admixture with blue, purple, or brown.
As the finger is pressed upon the surface, or pressed over it, toward the
heart, the rosy color is removed, leaving the structures clear and transparent,
and the color comes back quickly when the pressure ceases” (Scudder, 1985a,
77).
Scudder (1985b) uses case histories
to demonstrate his approach. He gives 18 cases under ague or intermittent
fever [malaria or influenza with periodic chills], 18 under remittent fever
[malaria or influenza with chills at odd intervals], 8 cases of continued fever
[septicemia], 4 cases of small pox, 6 of measles, 7 under rheumatism, 4 under
infantile pneumonia, 4 cases of infantile cholera, and 2 of dysentery. Very
seldom does he use the same two remedies in a row; he is trying to show how a
variety of remedies can be suited to different presentations of the same
disease or symptom picture.
Samuel Thomson (1769-1843), a
self-taught New Hampshire farmer who popularized herbal medicine in the
early United States, is generally considered to be the single most
influential figure in the history of nineteenth and early twentieth century
Western herbal medicine (Webb, 1916; Haller, 1997). He developed a materia
medica and theory of herbal treatment based on experience.
“Dr. Thomson began his practice as it were from
accident, with no other view than an honest endeavor to be useful to his fellow
creatures; and had nothing to guide him but his own experience” (Thomson,
1825a, 8).
Thomson developed his knowledge of
materia medica largely by tasting plants to see what their action upon himself
would be:
“I have adopted a rule to ascertain what is
good for canker [mucus coatings], which I have found very useful. . . . chew
some of the article, and if it causes the saliva to flow freely and leaves the
mouth clean and moist, it is good; but on the other hand, if it dries up the juices,
and leaves the mouth rough and dry, it is bad and should be avoided” (Thomson,
1825b, 55).
Notice how Thomson (1825b) adopted a
rule, based upon his experience. Unlike Scudder (1985a), he is concerned
throughout his work to discover rules and theories for practice:
“After I had come to the determination to make
a business of the medical practice, I found it necessary to fix upon some
system, or plan for my future government in the treatment of disease; for what
I had done had been as it were from accident and the necessity arising out of
the particular cases that came under my care, without any fixed plan” (Thomson,
1825a, 14).
The major health problem at the time
was fever, so Thomson’s theories were largely developed by dealing with that
condition.
“I found that fever was a disturbed state of
the heat, or more properly, that it was caused by the efforts which nature
makes to throw off disease, and therefore ought to be aided in its cause, and
treated as a friend; and not as an enemy, as is the practice of the physicians.
. . . All fevers proceed from the same cause, differing only in the symptoms;
and may be managed. . . with much less trouble than is generally considered”
(Thomson, 1825a, 15).
Thomson thus arrived at his method of
treatment:
“My general plan of treatment has been in all
cases of disease, to cleanse the stomach by giving No. 1 [Lobelia inflata],
and produce as great an internal heat as I could, by giving No. 2 [Capsicum
spp.], and when necessary made use of steaming [steam bath], in which I
have always found great benefit, especially in fevers; after this, I gave No. 3
[Myrica cerifera], to clear off the canker” (Thomson, 1825a, 15).
Thomson (1825a) also gives many case
histories scattered throughout the text. However, these mostly serve an
autobiographical purpose, illustrating how he learned something, or describing
his hard usage at the hands of physicians and ungrateful patients, or some
remarkable cure. In some instances, not enough information is given to
consider the case history illustrative of any medical lesson. At the end he
gives a group of case histories certified by witnesses. These provide
eyewitness testimony and contain few facts that are educational.
Another area in which empiricism enters
deeply into herbal medicine is the derivation of herb uses from tasting
plants. This takes two forms: sensing the taste and sensing the action.
Thomson, above, provides an example of an herbalist tasting a plant to
determine its action. The relationship of the taste of herbs has long been
considered empirical evidence of their properties. There is a long, but
forgotten history of this in Western herbalism (Crellin and Philpott, 1990); it
is also characteristic of Chinese herbalism (Bensky and Gamble, 1986), and
Ayurveda (Lad and Frawley, 1989). The author has observed several herbalists
teaching the properties of herbs by having their students taste them.
This author concludes that these
methods – case histories, descriptions of clinical experience, and the tasting
of plants – are widely but sporadically used in Western herbal medicine. He
suggests that modern herbalists develop this pragmatic methodology –
particularly in regard to case history documentation.
Case histories are not considered
without value in biomedicine. The single case history is often dismissed as
“anecdotal medicine,” but a series of cases (five being the minimum) is called
a “case series” and is considered to be the basis for further investigation
(Fugh-Berman, 1996, 8). There are scientific standards for making and
reporting observations, and keeping them as independent of bias and theory as
possible.
“Insofar as this activity is to contribute to
science it should be more fully put as ‘observational claim’ or ‘observational
belief’” (Kosso, 1992, 190).
Taken individually or together, the
empiricism of Hippocrates, Thomson, and Scudder bear some resemblance to the
approach of another traditional system, Chinese medicine (abbreviated ‘CM,’ or
‘TCM’). Here too the case history is important.
“If we examine, for instance, CM’s vast
literary corpus, we find that a significant part consists of case histories (yian).
An even larger part. . . cannot be assigned to any definite genre, but
contain a heterogeneous mix of commentary, theory, prescriptions, case
histories, philosophy, and so on” (Scheid, 1996, 10).
The same author ranks the use of the
case history in Chinese Medicine to obtain knowledge very highly:
“If the double blind trial is the gold standard
of biomedical research, than [sic] the single-case studies (SCS)
are the research paradigm of CM” (Scheid, 1996, 11).
Scheid (1996) likens the practice of
Chinese medicine to the practice of law, because it argues from case law,
experience, and judgment. In the eyes of the present author, this is an
equally useful metaphor for Western herbalism. Indeed, the incorporation of
modern scientific evidence and research into jurisprudence, without destroying
the traditional empirical foundation of the legal system, might be considered
an ideal model for the incorporation of biomedical research into the originally
empirical and traditional methodology of herbal medicine.
It should also be acknowledged that
empiricism is an important component of modern medical practice, even within
evidence-based medicine (Sackett, et al., 1997). Lown (1996) argues that it
has become undervalued. Ironically, while biomedicists allow empiricism within
their own practice, they do not generally extend the same standard to CAM
and herbal practitioners, as we saw by their discussion of research in section
6, ‘Paradigms and Biomedicine,’ (p. 10).
8.1.1. Empirical Research: Taste
Sir John Hill, in the mid-eighteenth
century, attempted to establish some order by which the medicinal properties of
plants might be rationally known. He suggested the use of taste.
“To give an instance in the marshmallow. It is
known to work by urine, and to be good against the gravel. We will suppose no
more known concerning this kind. A person desirous of extending this useful
knowledge, finds that by the taste of the root, which is insipid, and its
mucilaginous quality, he might have guessed this to be its virtue from what he
before knew of medicine” (Hill, 1789, 396).
Hill also explains that plants that
are similar in appearance are not only probably akin, but likely have similar
properties. Thus, the common mallow and hollyhock resemble marshmallow in the
construction of their flowers, and their tastes confirm similar uses (Hill,
1789, 396).
Although self-taught, taste was also
Thomson’s (1825a, 1825b) chief method of learning about plants. This is the
method he followed early in his practice when he adopted sumach (species not
given) to help him in a serious epidemic:
“The first of my knowledge that it was good for
canker was when at Onion River in 1807, attending the dysentery; being in want
of something to clear the stomach and bowels in that complaint, found that the
bark, leaves or berries answered the purpose extremely well, and have made much
use of it ever since” (Thomson, 1825b, 57).
Thomson (1825b, 55) went on to
classify sumach under a category he rather unimaginatively called “No. 3.” The
plants listed under this heading are generally what herbalists or physicians
call ‘astringents’ (Menzies-Trull, 2003), but the self-taught Thomson (1825b)
was not familiar with this term.
8.1.2. Empirical Research: Animal Use
It is often noted in books about
herbalism that humans learned about plants from watching animals use them
(Crellin and Philpott, 1990). However, actual examples of this are seldom
found in the literature. The author offers the following example.
Paul Red Elk (2005, personal
communication), was raised by his grandfather and grandmother, traditional
Lakota Indian herbalists on Rosebud Reservation, in western South Dakota. He explained that sumach (Rhus aromatica, R. typhina) is
an ‘elk’ or ‘deer’ medicine because it is used by the deer. It was observed that
the female deer, after giving birth, would eat sumach leaves and lick her
vagina. This led the Lakotas to believe that sumach helps “cleanse” the female
parts.
The use of sumach for afterbirth
infection, leucorrhea, menorrhagia, and vaginal hemorrhage is found in modern
herbal literature (Menzies-Trull, 2003; Fleming, 1998).
8.1.3. Empirical Research: Case Histories
In 1879, Dr. J. T. McClanahan
introduced sumach (Rhus aromatica) as a remedy for diabetes mellitus –
what we would now call ‘type II.’ Here is his account of the condition in an
elderly woman:
“Skin sallow, eyes sunken, pulse feeble and
quick, temperature 100.5˚, loss of flesh, slight cough, and sometimes
night-sweats, appetite variable, sometimes ravenous and sometimes not so good;
thirst, more or less, all the time; bowels sometimes constipated and sometimes
the contrary condition was present; there was also a general sense of lassitude
and languor. The history of the case revealed the fact that several months
previously her attention was first attracted by frequent calls to urinate, and
that she was compelled to get up at night to void large quantities of urine;
this condition of things had been steadily increasing, until she was compelled
to abandon her ordinary household duties. Under the usual tests the urine
revealed a large saccharine deposit, specific gravity 1031” (McClanahan, quoted
by Fyfe, 1909, 696).
Dr. McClanahan left a tincture of Rhus
aromatica, ten drops every four hours. At the end of a week her husband
reported that the urine was diminished and she was greatly improved, except for
a pain and soreness across the kidneys. McClanahan gave a blistering plaster
over the kidneys as a stimulant. At the end of four months the patient was in
decent health (McClanahan, cited by Fyfe, 1909).
The author located another case of
diabetes mellitus [type II] treated with Rhus aromatica (Goss, 1885).
He also documented from his own practice cases of palliation or improvement of
diabetes mellitus type II symptoms with Rhus typhina, and several cases
of improvement of diabetes insipidus (Wood, 2004).
From the biomedical standpoint, to
comprise a ‘case series’ the author would need to collect five case histories,
and these would need to illustrate a biomedical conception (Fugh-Berman,
1996). However, the author feels that it is important to point out that, from
the standpoint of holistic medicine, a case series could be organized around an
‘energetic’ feature. Thus, a case series for sumach could include various
symptoms of fluid loss, since it is widely classified as an astringent and
traditionally used to treat various kinds of fluid loss (Fyfe, 1909). Thus,
hemorrhaging from the vagina, excessive urination, diarrhea, and excessive
perspiration all could be used in a case series relating to sumach.
8.2. Rational Science
The use of rational theories to
structure medical practice is ancient. The Hippocratic writers lived during a
period of transition in science from empiricism to rationalism and theory. The
Hippocratic treatise Tradition in Medicine specifically challenges the
‘new’ hypothesis of the ‘four qualities’ (hot, cold, damp, dry) and treatment
by ‘contrary’ (hot to cold) then entering Greek medicine:
“They would suppose that there is some principle
harmful to man; heat or cold, wetness or dryness, and that the right way to
bring about cures is to correct cold with warmth, or dryness with moisture and
so on. . . the remedy lies in the application of the opposite principle
according to the hypothesis” (Hippocrates, 1950, 19).
The four ‘qualities’ had been
introduced into the natural sciences by Aristotle. He defines them, not as
physical sensations or entities, but as general principles operating in nature:
“Hot is that which associates things of the
same kind. . . while cold. . . associates homogeneous and heterogeneous things
alike. Fluid is that which, being readily adaptable in shape, is not
determinable by any limit of its own, while dry is that which is readily determinable
by its own limit, but readily adaptable in shape” (Aristotle, quoted by Mure,
1964, 73).
The present author interprets this to
mean that cold conjoins substances together that have nothing in common (like
water, a bug, and dirt in an ice cube), while heat separates them (water
becomes vapor, the bug and dirt become ash). Dry is that which gives shape,
while damp is that which lacks shape, but can be contained by shape. From the
Aristotelian perspective, water is damp when it is liquid and dry when it is
ice! This explains why the ‘qualities’ do not always make sense, in modern
terms, when they were applied in the old literature.
From Galen onwards, the four
qualities were the major classification system used to describe constitutions,
pathological changes in patients (too hot, too cold, etc.), the properties of
medicines (cooling, warming), and the method by which medicines worked (hot to
cold, etc.) (Cumston, 1987). The ‘qualities’ comprise a major part of the
‘energetic’ system of Greek medicine (Holmes, 1999).
Many of the descriptive terms used to
classify herbs in modern Western herbal literature were originally arranged
into categories by Galen, but that the organizational theme was lost when
Galenic medicine was rejected several hundred years ago (Cumston, 1987). The
author suggests that modern herbalists study this system to reclaim an
organizational perspective and enlarge their vocabulary for description of herb
activities.
An excellent overview of the Galenic method
for using herbs was written in 1652 by Nicholas Culpeper. This brief account,
entitled “A Key to Galen’s Method of Physic” (Culpeper, 1990, 376) defines
herbs under three major classes:
(1). Temperatures, the four qualities
and four degrees.
(2). Appropriations, or organ affinities
of the herbs.
(3). Properties (softening, hardening,
purging, loosening, contracting or binding or drawing, dispersing, repelling,
cleansing, agglutinative, preserving, nourishing, and diuretic).
The author believes that these simple
themes will help sort out the vast array of herbal terminology presently found
in Western herbalism, the logic for which was often forgotten when Galen’s
system was dropped by seventeenth century medicine. The author also recommends
study of the Thomsonian or physio-medical system, which offered a rationale
somewhat different from the Galenic.
In addition to recommending case
histories as the traditional research tool of Chinese medicine, Scheid (1996)
recommends “conceptual” research:
“Rather than being guided by dominant
biomedical ideologies, we need to build networks with anthropologists,
historians of medicine, sinologists, philosophers, sociologists of knowledge,
etc., to further our understanding of CM practice” (Scheid, 1996, 12).
The present author wholeheartedly
agrees with this recommendation. He has observed that most modern Western
herbalists have little understanding of traditional theories of Western
herbalism. This would explain the introduction of so many alternative theories
into herbal literature, noted in section 4, ‘Modern Western Herbalism,’ (p.
7). Hence, he suggests the arguments of Scheid (1996) can be fruitfully
applied to the study of Western herbalism.
A final point should be noted
regarding the theoretical approach to medicine. Rationalism can yield many
different interpretations, theories, and explanations for a single phenomenon.
Reise (1953) demonstrated that historical Western medicine had generated over a
dozen different theories of disease. Therefore, one no medical system can
claim that it is the only rational approach (Reise, 1953).
8.2.1. Research on Theory
Sumach (Rhus coriaria) was
used in traditional European herbalism (Gerard, 1975). Suppose a person wanted
to determine if the traditional European uses resemble the American
applications for Rhus aromatica, R. typhina, R. glabra, etc.
According to Gerard (1975), Galen
classified sumach as cold in the second degree, dry in the third, and binding.
The ‘degrees’ do not refer to increasing intensity of temperature or humidity,
but to the type of action. William Salmon (1710) offers a good description of
these technical terms. Cold in the second degree means that the remedy treats
fever, but does not relax the mind (third degree), or cause unconsciousness or
death (fourth degree). On the other hand, it can be used to cool on a hot
summer day (first degree). Dry in the third degree means that the plant treats
diarrhea and dysentery, but not fluid loss with cachexia, or consumption. The
term ‘binding’ refers to stopping diarrhea or dysentery.
These terms accurately describe the
use of the American sumachs for one of their most common applications: diarrhea
or dysentery (Thomson, 1825b). Fluid loss with fever (McClanahan, quoted by
Fyfe, 1909) is also described. In North
America it is not uncommon to make
a sour ‘lemonade’ during the hot, humid summer months with sumach berries
(Harris, 1976). Thus, the actions of the European and American sumachs seem to
be quite similar.
8.3. Experimental Science
Carr (1992) outlines three basic laws
of experimental research. First, the problem to be studied must be clearly
formulated in words. Second, the problem must be one that will yield useful
empirical data that can be identified and collected. Whenever possible, that
data should be numerical, so that idiosyncrasies and peculiarities can be
factored out statistically. Third, the events to be tested and collected must
be accessible to other observers, so that the results can be checked.
Today medical experimentation
includes such methods as survey (interviewing people on whom no intervention
has been made), retrospective studies (study of past events), prospective
studies (subjects or populations are followed into the future), pharmacological
research into constituents of plants and other medicinal substances, animal
trials, in vitro laboratory tests with bacteria and viruses, and
clinical trials (people are subjected to experimental intervention)
(Fugh-Berman, 1996).
Clinical trials are the final and
highest level of medical research (Fugh-Berman, 1996). Trials can be conducted
at varying levels of sophistication. In a controlled trial one group receives
the intervention and one does not. In a placebo-controlled trial the group
that does not receive the intervention receives a placebo. This helps to
eliminate bias and equalizes the curative effects of ‘treatment.’ The
intervention must be statistically proven more powerful than placebo, which
produces positive responses in one third of recipients! In a randomized trial
people are placed into two (or more) groups randomly, to prevent bias on the
part of the experimenters. In a double-blind study neither the subjects nor
the observers know which group is which. In order to produce statistically
significant results the sample size or groups measured must be large enough to
minimize the possibility that the results are due to chance. It is customary
to measure the results as probabilities. The ‘p value’ (p=probability) shows
the likelihood of the results being caused by chance. Thus,
“The gold standard for medical research is a
prospective, randomized, double-blind, placebo-controlled trial with a sample
size large enough to produce a p value of <.05 or lower” (Fugh-Berman, 1996,
14).
However, due to the expense involved
in setting up research, many conventional and alternative studies come nowhere
near ‘the gold standard’ (Fugh-Berman, 1996).
A change in the use of the experimental
method in medicine occurred in the 1990s, when the cyber revolution allowed the
collection and dissemination of massive amounts of data in minimal time. As
the number of experiments grew it became increasingly hard for the average
clinical physician to keep up with fast moving developments. Critics claimed
that medical prescriptions were often based on advertising by self-interested
drug companies. New computer technology made the accumulation and digestion of
massive amounts of information feasible. By the 1980s the new paradigm had
been envisioned; it was called “evidence-based medicine” (EBM). The
publication of a digest of results from randomized controlled trials occurred
in 1991. These changes made it possible to base medical practice on the most
recent research data supplied by experimentation (Davidoff, Haynes, Sackett,
Smith, 1995).
While EBM suggested that medicine
could be practiced on a more scientific basis, it still acknowledged a place
for clinical empiricism. A textbook on EBM notes:
“Good doctors use both individual clinical
expertise and the best available external evidence and neither alone is enough”
(Sackett, et al., 1997, 2).
EBM is used as a standard for the
study of complementary and alternative methods. Thus, we now see references to
‘evidence-based herbalism’ (Ernst, 2002). Although biomedicine allows the use
of clinical expertise in association with EBM in the practice of medicine, it
seldom allows admission into evidence of the clinical experience of CAM
practitioners – vide the biomedical journals quoted in section 6,
‘Paradigms and Biomedicine,’ (p. 10).
Some very important criticisms of the
application of the experimental method in medicine have appeared recently.
Angell (2004), a former editor of the NEJM (cited elsewhere as co-author
of an editorial demanding that nutritional supplements and herbs be tested like
drugs), attributes poor quality studies and outright fraud to the corruptive
influence of companies with huge financial stakes in the lucrative
pharmaceutical industry. More serious methodological errors are suggested by
Ioannidis, a faculty member of Tufts University, in an article with the controversial title,
“Why Most Published Research Findings Are False:”
“Simulations show that for most study designs
and settings, it is more likely for a research claim to be false than true.
Moreover, for many current scientific fields, claimed research findings may
often be simply accurate measures of the prevailing bias” (Ioannidis, 2005,
2(8):e124).
Ioannidis (2005) maintains that most
research methods produce results so short of statistical significance, that the
findings represent the opinions of the researchers, rather than reliable data.
Add to this Angell’s contention that pharmaceutical companies are intentionally
falsifying results and the picture is even murkier. She comes to a similar
conclusion:
“Too often, all we have is bias and hype”
(Angell, 2004, 114).
These problems may be contributing to
the mortality and injury now becoming endemic in medical practice. Studies
show that in 1999 doctors were the third leading cause of death in America
– 250,000 people a year, including over 100,000 from the negative effects of
drugs that were properly prescribed and 12,000 from unnecessary surgery
(Starfield, 2000).
The author asks: can a method
producing such carnage be considered a system of knowledge – a science?
8.3.1. Pharmacological Research
Few herbalists will ever do research on pharmacological constituents,
but a student might want to determine whether modern research on sumach
verifies traditional herbal usage. The PDR for Herbal
Medicine (Fleming, 1998) gives
the following account of Rhus aromatica:
“COMPOUNDS
“Tannins (8%)- phenol glycosides: orcinol-beta-D-glucoside-volatile
oil (0.01-0.07%); very complex in mixture, with, including among others
delta-cadinene, camphene, Delta3-carene, beta-elemene, farnesyl acetone, alpha
and beta-pinine, fatty acids.
“Triterpenes: including among others oleanolic aldehyde.
“Sterols: including among others beta-sitosterol.
“EFFECTS
“Sweet Sumach has an effect on the smooth muscles, causing changes
in muscle tone and increased frequency of contraction. The plant also has
antimicrobial and antiviral effects.
“INDICATIONS AND USAGE
“Irritable bladder, urinary incontinence. Universal use in treating
kidney and bladder ailments, hemorrhage of the womb.
“Uses have not been proven through clinical studies or sufficient
case documentary” (Fleming, 1998, 1065).
The high percentage of tannins alone explain the traditional
applications of sumach as an astringent to prevent fluid loss. The complexity
of these tannins might account for the wide applicability of sumach in many
types of fluid loss.
Evidence-based medicine would
encourage the student to take a further step to determine whether there have
been additional pharmacological, clinical, or case studies. The present author
checked through ‘Google scholar’ (keywords ‘sumach’ and ‘sumac’) for more
recent papers on sumach and found no major increase in medical information.
8.3.2. Clinical Trials and Herbal Medicine
A study in Australia
looked at the treatment of patients with irritable bowel syndrome using Chinese
herbal medicine (‘CHM’). Researchers set up a double blind randomized
controlled trial with three groups, one treated by placebo, one with a single
Chinese herbal formula, and one in which patients were given a formula
individualized for them by one of three trained Chinese herbalists. All patients
received an individualized assessment but not the individualized formula.
Results were positive:
“Compared with patients in the placebo group, patients
in the active treatment groups (standard and individualized CHM) had
significant improvement in bowel symptom scores as rated by patients (P=.03)
and by gastroenterologists (P=.002). Patients reported that treatment
significantly reduced the degree of interference with life caused by IBS
symptoms (P=.03). Chinese herbal formulations individually tailored to the
patient proved no more effective than standard CHM treatment. On follow-up 14
weeks after completion of treatment, only the individualized CHM treatment
group maintained improvement” (Bensoussan, Talley, Hing, Menzies, Guso, Ngu,
1998, 280(18):1589).
This study attempts to work within
the holistic paradigm of individualized treatment. The authors intentionally
utilized the services of three herbalists, each with different training and
background, since that is normative practice in CHM. Consequently, this study
may be recommended as an example upon which to design research of herbalism and
CAM. However, biomedicists have not largely pursued the opportunity.
The author suggests that this is because such studies empower another
profession (in this case, Chinese herbalists), rather than biomedicists. Milton
(1996) collected many examples of research suppressed for professional
self-protection.
8.4. Visionary Science
The use of visions and dreams to derive information about the
natural world was (and still is) an accepted method in indigenous America.
Seeking a vision or dream which gives a person’s life meaning is called a
‘vision quest.’ When Lakota medicine man Wallace Black Elk was asked how he
learned about the powers of different plants he replied:
“Through a vision quest. It takes years. If
you want to carry the power, you make your commitment” (Weiss and Weiss, 1992,
35).
An Anishinabe Ojibwe elder speaking
to a folklorist in the upper peninsula of Michigan in 1951 described the use of dream in
traditional Indian society. He likened the process to going to school.
Children were asked to relate their dreams to their elders. At large yearly
sociopolitical gatherings, dreamers were queried by experts in the community to
see what meaning their dreams had for the individual or the community. The
elder likened the process to when
“a lawyer goes before the bar” (Dorson,
1951, 32).
Note the use of ‘peer review’ (so
important in science) to evaluate the significance of dreams.
The visionary approach is widely used
in contemporary Amazonia, where Indian cultures are comparatively
intact. It is also used by South American mestizo practitioners.
Ethnobotanists and pharmacologists working in Amazonia have been
shocked that illiterate herbalists exhibit an understanding of complex
pharmacological relationships. When asked how they learned about these
phenomena, Indian and mestizo practitioners explained that the plants told them
in dreams, visions, or hallucinations (Narby, 1998).
In 1984 Luna documented this practice
among mestizo vegetalistas (mixed-blood herbalists):
“The spirits, who are sometimes called doctorcitos
(little doctors) or abuelos (grandfathers) present themselves during the
visions and during the dreams. They show how to diagnose the illness, what
plants to use and how, the proper use of tobacco smoke, how to suck out the
illness or restore the spirit to a patient, how the shamans defend themselves,
what to eat, and, most important, teach them icaros, magic songs or
shamanic melodies which are the main tools of shamanic practices” (Luna, quoted
by Narby and Huxley, 2004, 229).
One ayahuasquero (shaman) commented that because vegetalistas
learn directly from the plants, it is thought that vegetalismo (herbalism)
is more powerful than la medicina destudio (biomedicine), since the
latter is reputedly learned only from books. Another explained that the
information comes directly from God:
“In nature, there is God, and God talks to us
in our visions. When an ayahuasquero drinks his plant brew, the spirits
present themselves to him and explain everything” (Narby, 1998, 24).
The use of vision and dream in
ancient European science and medicine is not as frequently encountered as it is
in Indian America. However, Pliny (c. 50 CE) acknowledged this method of
discovery of herbal properties:
“We are for some of them beholden to mere
chance and fortune: and for others (to say a truth) to the immediate revelation
from God” (Turner, 1992, 225).
Pliny cites an example of the latter:
“It fortuned of late, that a soldier, one of
the guard about the Praetorium, was bitten with a mad dog, and his mother saw a
vision in her sleep, giving (as it were) direction unto her for to send the
root unto her son for to drink, of an eglantine or wild rose (called
cynorrhodon) which the day before she had espied growing in a hortyard, where
she took pleasure to behold it. This occurrent fell out in Lacetania, the
nearest part unto us of Spain. Now, as God would, when the soldier beforesaid
upon his hurt received by the dog, was ready to fall into that symptom of
hydrophobia, and began to fear water; there came a letter from his mother,
advertising him to obey the will of God, and to do according to that which was
revealed unto her by the vision. Whereupon he drank the root of the said sweet
briar or eglantine, and not only recovered himself beyond all men’s
expectations: but also afterwards as many as in that case took the like receipt,
found the same remedy” (Turner, 1992, 224).
The author submits this as an
illustration of the visionary process, but admits that it is of little
practical value. The assertion that wild rose cures rabies would probably be
impossible to test and few herbalists today would ever have need to use it!
The use of the revelatory paradigm is
not unknown in modern Western herbalism. One influential American herbalist,
the late William LeSassier, derived a complete system of herbal formulation
from a vision:
“My first wife and I had just had a terrible
fight. After a while I fell back on the bed. . . all of a sudden I was glued
to the bed and a golden light, like the sun, but a golden triangle came down.
Out stepped a clothed figure dressed in many shades of green. Said he was
Pythagorus. Hands me this book. It was full of diagrams and formulas. . .
nine fold formulations. My wife kept on going, I just wrote it down. Up to
that time I was really stumped. It allowed me to make formulas. I wasn’t even
on drugs. Since then I’ve never had any doubt about. . . compounding”
(LeSassier, 2001, n.p.)
Several contemporary herbalists teach
students how to communicate with plants to gain information (Cowan, 1995;
Buhner, 1996). Both of these authors associate their methods with American
Indian practices or teachers.
The use of the visionary faculty to
obtain insight is not completely unrecorded within the annals of conventional
science. The chemist Friedrich August Kekule actively used the hypnogogic
state (visions seen just before falling asleep or waking up) to help him
understand chemistry. Here is his description of how he came to understand the
chemical structure of benzene:
“I turned my chair to the fire and dozed.
Again the atoms were gamboling before my eyes. The smaller groups kept
modestly in the background. My mental eye, rendered more acute by visions of
this kind, could now distinguish larger structures, of manifold conformations;
long rows, sometimes more closely fitted together, all twining and twisting in
snakelike motion. But look! What was that? One of the snakes had seized hold
of its own tail, and the form whirled mockingly before my eyes. As if by a
flash of lightning I awoke” (quoted by Koestler, 1964, 118).
Kekule’s visionary state resembles
descriptions by Amazonian Indians learning pharmacology under the influence of
hallucinogens. They too frequently saw writhing snakes forming structures
similar to complex organic molecules (Narby, 1998).
The visionary experience is not
unique among scientists:
“Many scientists have described to me their own
experiences resembling that of Kekule” (Needleman, 2003, 106).
As mentioned in subsections 8.1 to
8.3, the empirical, rational, and experimental paradigms are largely used to
provide a kind of ‘proof’ in science through observation, reasoning, isolation
of variables, and demonstration. In comparison, it does not appear that the
above visionaries and dreamers used their experiences for ‘proof,’ but rather for
insight, the solution of problems, and inspiration. Most of them considered
‘proof’ to be provided by the successful application of the revelation in
practice. As long as vision and dream are not used to provide proof, it seems
to the author that there cannot be any reasonable opposition to their use
either in conventional science or modern herbalism to enhance creativity.
8.4.1. Visionary Research
The only source describing systematic
visionary research in the contemporary herbal field that the author could find
was Cowan (1995). The following is an example of his work:
“My dream of St. Johnswort was short and
simple. A disembodied voice told me, ‘I will bind together that which has been
rent asunder.’ Since that time I have used it as cement for fractured souls.
It works wonders in cases of soul loss, husband/wife imbalance [an energetic
imbalance within a person], possession, and other situations” (Cowan, 1995,
126).
After recounting this dream, Cowan (1995) cites a
case history illustrating the successful application of the dream.
According to his book, Cowan (1995)
persistently interprets his plant visions to refer to psychological or
spiritual states in his patients, although – as is observable in the above
account – the plant does not limit itself to that application. Traditionally, St. John’s
wort is used for wounds, especially those involving nerves (Fyfe, 1909;
Hoffmann, 2003). The present author was struck, however, by his own experience
of the appropriateness of the above ‘statement’ by St. John’s
wort. This is the first herb he would use if a part of the physical body were
torn or severed and needed ‘cement.’
8.5. Analogical Science
This approach is characterized by the
use of ‘similars and analogies’ (Eamon, 1994; Kuhn, 1977). In other words,
meaning is derived from the resemblance between two natural entities that are
similar or analogous in appearance, growth habit, or other physical traits.
This technique can be employed in various ways. Some thinkers (such as Francis
Bacon), describe analogies that have a rational, causal relationship. The
present author refers to this as the ‘analogical’ approach. Others (such as
Paracelsus), seek out similarities in which there is no rational or causal
relationship. Paracelsus called his approach magia naturalis or
‘natural magic’ (Pagel, 1982). The author has followed him, referring to
non-causal similarity as the ‘magical’ approach. The author suggests that
these two methods are not entirely unrelated to each other but lie on a
continuum.
Previous authors, perhaps thinking
that ‘similars and analogies’ only occur in the imagination, lumped the
analogical/magical method together with the visionary approach. However, the
present author believes that the analogical and magical procedures are a form
of intuitive thinking, and that it is important to differentiate between this
and the visionary paradigm.
The magical approach forms a very
definite tradition in European science, reaching a zenith in the Hermetic literature
of Imperial Rome, and again in the Renaissance literature of Paracelsian
natural magic (Pagel, 1982).
Paracelsus (1493-1542) is generally
considered to be the chief representative of the use of similars and analogies
(Pagel, 1982). He developed special vocabulary to express his conceptions.
Accordingly, the physical form, shape, appearance, growth habit, color,
texture, etc., of a stone, plant, animal, or human, yields a signature or
sign that points to its hidden identity, essential nature, archetype, or essence.
The disease also has a characteristic signature demonstrating its nature.
Every natural entity has its own essence or archetype and therefore the natural
world as a whole is the outward expression through signatures of an entire and
complete archetypal world. The latter is called the macrocosm (greater
world), while the individual or the human race is a microcosm (lesser
world) (Pagel, 1982).
For Paracelsus, the curative
properties of the plant are found in the similarity of the healing agent to a
person, organ, or symptom. Thus, his healing credo is ‘like treats like’ (similia
similibus curantur), opposed to the Galenic ‘hot to cold’ (Pagel, 1982).
Here is an example of the Paracelsian method:
“Behold the Satyrion root, is it not
formed like the male privy parts? No one can deny this. Accordingly magic
discovered it and revealed that it can restore a man’s virility and passion”
(Paracelsus, 1958, 122).
The rhizome of Cypripedium spp. (satyrion,
lady’s slipper), which suggests the appearance of a testicle, is not used at
present due to environmental concerns. However, its reputation as a remedy for
sexual dysfunction of a nervous or psychological character (in both sexes)
survived into modern times (Fyfe, 1909).
Paracelsus not only claims that magic
discovers the signatures, essences, and similarities which heal, but rejects
literal, physical, or causal resemblance as a basis for similarity:
“Not the brain of a cow, not the brain of a
swine to the brain of a man, but the brain in the external world [macrocosm]
to man’s brain [microcosm]” (Paracelsus, quoted by Wood, 2005, 23).
In other words, a plant that looks
like a brain would be medicine for the brain of a human being, but the brain of
a cow would not. For example, peony (Paeonia spp.) is used to treat the
brain because the flower bud looks like a cranium (Harris, 1976).
The sense in which Paracelsus uses
the term ‘magic’ is in agreement with the definition offered by Frazier in The
Golden Bough:
“Analysis shows that magic rests everywhere on
two fundamental principles: first, that like produces like, effect
resembling cause; second, that things which have once been in contact
continue ever afterwards to act on each other” (Frazier, 1961, 5).
From this definition can be derived
two separate magical principles, which Frazier called the “law of similarity”
and the “law of contact” or “contagious magic” (Frazier, 1961, 5). ‘Magic,’ as
defined both by Paracelsus (1958) and Frazier (1961), implies a nonmaterial,
non-causal explanation, experience, or world. In this paper the word ‘magic’
will be used to describe non-causal relationships due to similarity, or a world
view based on that principle. It will not be used in a vague, ill-defined fashion
to represent ‘enchantment,’ ‘mystery,’ or ‘irrational,’ unless noted.
Although the Paracelsian essences are
hidden, they shine forth through the signatures, like a metaphorical light.
This may have inspired the Paracelsian image of the “light of nature” (Pagel,
1982, 55), one of the most elegant concepts of natural magic. In 1652 the
English alchemist Thomas Vaughan wrote:
“The Light of Nature. . . is the Secret Candle
of God, which He hath tinned in the elements: it burns and is not seen, for it
shines in a dark place. Every natural body is a kind of black lantern; it
carries this Candle within it, but the light appears not: it is eclipsed with
the grossness of the matter” (Vaughan, 1968, 266).
Frances Bacon (1561-1626) is
remembered for his contributions to the reductionistic method of experimental
science (Henry, 2002). However, he too advocated the use of similars and
analogies to counteract the tendency of experimental thinking to result in a
fragmentary view of nature:
“Our labor must be entirely redirected to
investigating and noting the similarities and analogies of things, both in
whole things and in their parts. For it is they that unify Nature and are the
origin and foundations of the sciences” (Bacon, 1994, 194).
Here is an example of Bacon’s (1994)
analogical method:
“That remarkable structure by which the sexes
differ (at least in land animals) appears simply to follow from one being
external and the other internal; that is to say, the greater heat in the male
pushes the genitalia to the outside, while in females the heat is too faint to
enable it to do this, with the result that they are contained within” (Bacon,
1994, 193).
The reader will observe that Bacon
(1994) is proposing a causal, physical relationship in his analogy. He
differentiates his kind of analogy from the
“superstitious or curious similarities, such as
are everywhere paraded by writers on natural magic” (Bacon., 1994,
194).
Probably he has in mind someone like Paracelsus,
the founder of natural magic.
Although Bacon (1994) rejects the
‘magical,’ non-causal use of analogy, he was influenced by natural magic
(Henry, 2002) and at times he writes like a natural magician:
“Truth should be sought, not
in the felicity of any particular age, which is a variable thing, but in the
light of Nature and experience, which is eternal” (Bacon, 1994, 63).
If Bacon (1994) did not believe in
the superstitious and curious excesses of the analogical approach, then what
was he thinking when he described the light of Nature as the source of truth
and eternity independent of variability and experience? The author suggests
that even the most restrained use of the analogical method may be invested with
a faint trace of ‘magic.’
The author suggests that the modus
operandi behind the analogical/magical approach is the intuition. The
certainty felt by Paracelsus, Vaughan, and Bacon in this method is described by
Jung (1976) as a characteristic of the intuition:
“Intuitive knowledge possesses an intrinsic
certainty and conviction, which enabled Spinoza (and Bergson) to uphold the scientia
intuitiva as the highest form of knowledge. Intuition shares this quality
with sensation. . . whose certainty rests on its physical foundations”
(Jung, 1976, 453).
The intuition is frequently
associated with the capacity to make mental connections between things or ideas
previously not evident (Jung, 1976).
A subsequent thinker who advocated an
intuitive approach to science was J. W. Goethe (1749-1832). His ‘scientific
method’ was largely ignored in the nineteenth century, but has been
resuscitated and today enjoys a modest following under the name “Goethean
science” (Whitelegg, 2003, 311).
Goethe felt that empirical
observation and rational analysis were incomplete. He advocated examination of
both the external and internal impressions a thing made upon the observer.
Goethe felt it was necessary to allow the internal faculties to complete their
analysis of a phenomena, and not to cut them off, as he felt was customary in
conventional science (Whitelegg, 2003).
The first step in Goethe’s process is
a detailed empirical observation of the phenomena, analogous to the modern
scientific concept of ‘informed observation.’ After finishing this, the
observers are to let their imagination and intuition play upon the phenomena.
Goethe was convinced that the mind would naturally gravitate towards the
inherent idea or urphaenomenon (primordial nature) of a thing.
The final step in the Goethean process involves comparison of imaginative and
intuitive data by different people examining the same subject. The expectation
is that different people will have similar subjective reactions to it (Storl,
1990; Whitelegg, 2003).
The word ‘subjective’ is used with
some hesitance by the author. From the Goethean perspective,
“The proper Idea belonging to the phenomenon
[is] as objective as is the phenomenon itself” (Storl, 1990, 94).
Here again we see the tendency of the intuitive
experience to yield results of a ‘certainty,’ as described by Jung (1976). The
essence of the thing can be as real to the intuitive as a physical sensation
(Jung, 1976).
The intuitive reality of the
archetype cannot, of course, be substantiated by material observation. When
Plato introduced the concept of the idea (the ancestor of Goethe’s idea),
Diogenes the Dog offered the retort:
“I’ve seen Plato’s cups and table, but not his
cupness and tableness” (Davenport, 1979, 57).
This kind of criticism does not, in
the author’s mind, negate the intuitive approach. It still may be of value in
establishing relationship and context not evident in a purely physical
examination. The author would further suggest that such distinctive concepts
as ‘ideas,’ ‘archetypes,’ and ‘signatures’ be looked upon as ‘tools’ of the
intuitive approach, rather than as real or unreal entities. Just as scientific
experimentation uses tools (trials, double-blind, the p-value, etc.) to arrive
at research conclusions, a mature view would allow intuitive investigation the
use of its own well-defined methods to arrive at intuitive conclusions. As
Whitelegg (2003, 320) comments, the doctrine of signatures may have to be
“reassessed.”
Analogical and magical approaches
have had an extensive influence on herbalism and pre-modern science. The use
of the doctrine of signatures in traditional herbalism is nearly ubiquitous
(Crellin and Philpott, 1990). Modern herbalists, following the cue of
scientists, have tried to ignore signatures, but even today it has advocates
(Harris, 1972; Wood, 2004, 2005).
8.5.1. Analogical Research
In the 1990s the author was first
approached by clients diagnosed with Lyme disease. This is a deer-borne
syphilis spread to humans through the bite of the tiny deer tick (Buhner,
2005). Lacking guidance from pharmacology or tradition, the author was forced
to use his wits. He employed tradition, analogy, and the doctrine of
signatures to find a remedy.
The author reasoned that a remedy for
Lyme ought to be good for the muscles and joints, which Lyme destroys. Teasel (Dipsacus
japonica) is used for injured muscles and joints in Chinese herbalism
(Bensky and Gamble, 1986). The author already had good experience using Dipsacus
sylvestris (naturalized in his area) for these problems. Teasel is also
discussed in the same source as a support for the ‘jing’ or essence, which the
author understood to be a sort of ‘genetic blueprint’ particularly susceptible
to attack by syphilis. He also knew, from conversations with American Indians,
that thistles like teasel are often considered ‘elk medicines.’ These
indications appealed to his intuition and induced him to try Dipsacus
sylvestris (naturalized in his area) for Lyme disease.
Today the use of teasel for Lyme is
widespread. A Google search under the words “teasel” and “Lyme” yielded
95,700 hits on December 21, 2005.
8.6. Authoritarian Science
The success of science has
contributed to its credibility and authority in society (Kosso, 1992).
However, the use of authoritarianism in scientific argumentation, in lieu of
factual evidence, is classified as a major scientific fallacy (Carr, 1992).
The authority granted by society, plus the misuse of authoritarian
argumentation has often produced very unscientific science (Milton,
1996). The latter has collected many interesting examples. For instance, for
five years after the Wright brothers began flying airplanes in broad daylight,
in front of hundreds of witnesses, they were ignored by the media, government,
and general public because contemporary scientists declared that
heavier-than-air flight was impossible. In the 1990s Ornish developed dietary
and lifestyle methods to prevent and treat heart disease but the American Heart
Association refused to fund his research because they declared heart disease
impossible to prevent or treat.
From extensive evidence, Milton
(1996) concluded that a ‘scientific taboo’ towards innovative and unusual
information, methods, and people was characteristic in many fields:
“The taboo reaction draws a circle around a
subject and places it ‘out of bounds’ to any form of rational analysis or
investigation. . . . This form of scientific taboo is best seen in the
prohibition against investigating any form of electromagnetic field associated
with living organisms, when there is actually very substantial physical
evidence for such a field” (Milton, 1996, 84).
This provides an explanation for why
biomedicists refuse to study CAM paradigms, persons, and experiences. To engage
in conversation grants the opponent authority. As Milton
(1996) demonstrates in several instances, professionals in one field, feeling
threatened by developments in another, attempt to suppress the work to guard
their own turf. This is true even when the other field is relatively unrelated
to their own. Airplanes were invented by bicycle mechanics, not scientists.
Furthermore, media and the public tend to view scientists, even when expressing
opinions outside their field, as ‘experts’ (Milton, 1996).
The misuse of authority in science
has often been commented upon. What is surprising is that authoritarianism can
play a creative role in the evolution of science. This is particularly
the case during periods of scientific revolution, when new perspectives
challenge entrenched authority. The scientific revolution of the Renaissance
was deeply inspired by the idea that scientists were recovering the ‘lost
knowledge’ of ancient authorities, when in fact they were often misinterpreting
them to develop important new ideas. It is possible that scientific revolution
would be too intimidating for some of its proponents if they did not think they
were reestablishing sound practices from the past. The phenomenon of
scientific growth through supposed ‘recovery of ancient wisdom,’ often
resulting in profound misinterpretations which, nonetheless, significantly
advance science, has been described as “archeological science” (Schmidt, 2005,
personal communication).
The reverse also may to be true.
Some find authority in the ‘latest’ research developments. This is the
supposition behind evidence-based medicine (Sackett, et al., 1997). However,
it is also possible to place too much authority in the ‘latest’ developments.
When they are greeted uncritically, there can be
“an arrogance of the present” (Kosso, 1992, 3).
These examples suggest that
authoritarianism should be viewed as a many faceted complex that can have both
positive and negative influences upon science.
When the authority of the past
extends unbroken to the present (and need not be recovered), the author would
describe it a as tradition. The importance of authority and its analogue,
tradition, are apparent in Western herbalism. The ancient authors –
Hippocrates, Dioscorides, Plinius, and Galen – are cited by Renaissance authors
(Gerard, 1975; Culpeper, 1990; Salmon, 1710), who are in turn cited by
twentieth century writers (Grieve, 1994, Harris, 1976).
The twentieth century saw a break in
herbal tradition. This is indicated, the author suggests, by the large number
of publications cited in this paper seeking tradition and authority from a
variety of sources – physio-medicalism, eclecticism, traditional Chinese
medicine, Ayurveda, Greek medicine, biomedicine, American Indians, witches
burned at the stake, wise women, a vision of Pythagorus, nature, etc.
Ironically, in seeking authority
outside Western herbalism, innovative authors were rejecting an established
tradition. Tommie Bass, the old Georgia folk herbalist interviewed by Crellin and
Philpott (1990), mistrusted practices not grounded in tradition.
“Bass is unappreciative of the many
practitioners who have become part of the present-day wholistic [sic] movement
without a clear lineage from the past” (Crellin and Philpott, 1990, 1:85).
The author concludes that both the
adherence of the older herbalist to his inherited tradition, and the search for
tradition among younger herbalists, indicate that tradition is an important
criteria for validity in herbal medicine.
The author points to a possible
danger from discarding traditional knowledge. The introduction of herbal
products into the marketplace, based solely on scientific theory or research,
without reference to tradition or experience, may be a formula for failure.
The research histories of two different plants illustrate this problem.
8.6.1. Biomedical Research and Herbal Tradition
Elder (Sambucus nigra) has
long been used in European folk medicine for fevers, influenza, and respiratory
conditions (Grieve, 1994). A number of constituents (cyanogenetic glucosides,
flavonoids, cytokinens) suggest antifebrile and antiviral properties (Hoffman,
2003). In a study in 1995, Sambucol (a standardized elderberry extract) showed
positive results in inhibiting the growth of ten different strains of influenza
virus. Clinical trials demonstrated that it lessened the length of
recuperation and discomfort from influenza.
“A significant improvement of the symptoms,
including fever, was seen in 93.3% of the cases in the SAM[Sambucol]-treated
group within 2 days, whereas in the control group 91.7% of the patients shows
an improvement within 6 days (p < 0.001)” (Zakay-Rones, Varsano, Zlotnik,
Manor, Regev, Schlesinger, and Mumcuoglu, 1995, 4:361).
In this research the confluence of
tradition and modern pharmacology can be observed. Conversely, ignoring the
historical, empirical, and paradigmatic context of a plant or therapy could led
to disappointment. An example of this is demonstrated in research on
echinacea. In 2004, the largest pediatric study ever conducted to date
concluded that echinacea showed no benefit in the treatment of upper
respiratory tract symptoms in children. One of the participants in this study
was Bastyr University, a naturopathic (holistic) medical school
(Dubik, 2004). The following year an exhaustive study published in the NEJM
concluded that echinacea showed no clinically significant effect in
rhinovirus infections (Turner, Bauer, Woelkart, Thomas, Gangemi, 2005). This
was followed by an editorial in the same journal that stated,
“Tracing the evolution of views about the
benefits of echinacea from the traditions of indigenous populations to modern
claims, one finds little rationale for studying the effects of this herbal
remedy on colds” (Sampson, 2005, 353:337).
Sampson is correct: echinacea was not
traditionally used for head colds (Fyfe, 1909). This usage is based on
pharmacological speculation about the possible uses of its ‘active
constituents,’ i.e., polysaccharide immunostimulants (Fleming, 1998). If
scientists had placed a higher value on traditional reports about echinacea,
perhaps its use on apparently specious grounds might have been
avoided.
Ironically, Sampson (2005) takes
these high profile findings as evidence that CAM is bogus and the
study of herbal remedies a waste of resources. Yet, according to his own
statement, traditional medicine had nothing to do with this debacle. Who,
then, is responsible?
The present author suggests it would
be more appropriate to consider the role of commercial interests who have
marketed echinacea. Angell (2004) refers to the corruptive influence of
commerce in the drug industry. CAM practitioners and advocates who have recommended
echinacea for head colds may have been misled, not by traditional or
empirical herbalism, but by speculation fanned by commercialism.
This raises an important question.
If so-called CAM practitioners derive their information from modern
biomedical sources, without reference to tradition or holism, are they
advocates of biomedicine or complementary and alternative medicine?
9. Discussion.
This paper is about the
knowledge-gathering methods available to the herbalist. Scientifically
oriented biomedical writers have attempted to enforce a strict methodology on
the study of herbal medicines, allowing only pharmacological study and clinical
trials while frequently ignoring or disallowing into evidence herbal
experience, tradition, and holistic paradigms. It has been suggested that this
restrictive methodology is inappropriate for several important reasons, and
should be rejected by the herbal community.
Although biomedicine recognizes the
need for empiricism in its own practice, it rejects empiricism in the study and
use of herbs. It haphazardly refers to herbal experience and tradition and
ignores the opinions and experiences of herbalists. Although a clinical trial
model has been designed and used allowing inclusion of holistic characteristics
of herbal practice, this model has been little used. The author suggests that
this may be due to professional bias. Serious problems with biomedical
research have been raised by Ionnides and Angell. Consequently, the author
advocates that herbalists should not limit themselves to the biomedical model,
but should retain traditional methods of knowledge-gathering, and oppose
biomedical manipulation of their field.
This paper has researched and defined
three basic classes of knowledge-gathering used in herbal medicine:
traditional methods of herbalism,
biomedical methods, and
revelatory methods.
This paper advocates that all these
methods be used in modern Western herbalism.
The traditional methods were
described by Crellin and Philpott (1990) and confirmed in the present study.
They are:
empiricism
rationalism or theory
tradition based on empiricism and theory
The present author suggests that
these methods have carried herbalism along in the past, and are relatively
scientific, even from a conventional perspective, since they are primarily
dependent on experience and observation. As Kuhn (1970) maintains, older
methods of science are not canceled out by newer methods, but remain
scientific. Empirical knowledge is not canceled out by experimental research.
However, the author suggests that herbalists need to develop deeper knowledge
of modern scientific use of empirical data. They would also need to learn to
interpret theories used to organize herbal knowledge in the past but have not
been sufficiently explained for a modern audience, such as the Galenic and
Thomsonian methods.
The biomedical methods are
sufficiently described by sources explaining scientific procedure (Carr, 1992;
Kosso, 1992; Fugh-Berman, 1996):
empiricism
rationalism
experimentation
Science and herbalism are in relative
agreement about the use of empiricism, though this element appears to be
wrongly ignored by biomedicists in the study of herbalism. It need not be
abandoned by herbalists. However, herbalists should learn more about
scientific standards of evidence in empirical and observational research.
Greater attention should be placed on the development of case series.
The revelatory methods have
been routinely rejected by modern science and medicine. They have also been
largely ignored by herbal medicine up to last quarter of the twentieth century,
probably because herbalism was closely conjoined with conventional science and
medicine until recently. However, it was shown that these methods (vision and
intuition) are capable of constructive use. The latter, via the doctrine of
signatures, has long played a recognized (or unrecognized, underground?) role
in herbalism. It can be acknowledged today with the return to a more holistic,
intuitive view of nature. Intuition can be developed through the Goethean
method.
It should be noted that empiricism,
vision, and intuition are more ‘participatory’ than other methods of
knowledge-gathering; they draw a person into nature and can increase the sense
of connectedness to the natural world (Cajete, 2000). Hence, the use of these
methods should be considered to strengthen the natural and holistic elements in
herbalism. By embracing different methods of perceiving and interacting with
the natural world herbalism makes itself more professionally holistic – it can
accept different people and different methods of human intelligence, both in
practitioners and in clientele.
The use of ‘participatory’ methods
also brings herbalism into a closer relationship with the plant, encouraging a
more holistic experience of medicinal agents. Rather than viewing medicinal
plants as bags of chemical constituents to be broken up and reductionistically
studied, herbalists may retain a view of them as whole beings, valuable in
their wholeness. The author suggests that more study could be made of the
differences between the use of constituent parts and the whole herb.
There is an additional reason to
embrace the use of all possible methods of herbal knowledge-gathering: to
improve certainty in the understanding and application of herbs. Among the
foregoing methods the author can discern at least three different standards for
relative levels of certainty in the use of medicinal substances.
The first of these is the scientific
method, based upon the use of the ‘gold standard’ for biomedical research, the
double blind clinical trial. This is advocated by leading biomedical journals,
yet the evidence so far produced by this method is not encouraging.
Controversy swirls around echinacea, critics have identified major flaws and
biases in biomedical trial methods, commercialism may be interfering in drug
and herbal studies, and biomedical bias against other professions may be
influencing research. Expense is an increasing consideration. We may not be
in an era when this methodology can produce its best results.
The second method of certainty is
empirical: ‘it works.’ Greater efforts could be made by herbalists to
incorporate positive results in the form of case series studies. These may be
arranged both according to biomedical and holistic/energetic standards.
The third method of certainty is the
intuitive: ‘it makes sense.’ Bias against this approach has led to its being
ignored by conventional science on the premise that the intuitive faculty is
subjective. However, the intuition has great potential and is commonly used
for knowledge-gathering in social settings. If it can be carefully integrated
with the scientific method, as is suggested by Goethean science, then it should
be embraced by science and herbalism.
A fourth method emphasizes the
importance of using more than one approach: the confluence of similar results
from several different methods would be a source of certainty not available
from the restrictive use of a single method. A science based on ‘confluent
research’ (do we have here a new paradigm?) could have strength and
depth.
10. Conclusions
This paper has examined various
methods of knowledge-gathering available to the herbalist. The author
concludes that all these methods can be used responsibly, and that their
development within Western herbalism can contribute to a profession
conceptually stronger, holistically founded, and more certain in its application
of plant medicines. He suggests that the ‘confluence’ of several approaches
would provide better evidence for use of herbs than the employment of one or
two methods alone.
In addition, the author finds that
the application of the biomedical model to herbal medicine as a sole
methodology is inappropriate. He suggests that this approach is in part
designed to disempower herbalism. Changes in the method necessary for unbiased
and successful research are suggested. The author demonstrates that these
methods have already been successfully implemented.
These results address the questions
the author set out to answer. However, he was driven to additional conclusions
he did not anticipate. Specifically, he concluded that some methods of research
would be more fruitful for herbalism than others. This finding pertains
especially to the use of the case series method, a form of empirical research
that not only satisfies scientific standards but provides herbalists with
information useful in the clinic. The author offers his observational belief,
as an herbal teacher and writer, that case histories are a powerful tool in the
education of students.
The present study was not designed to
establish this result and it was not anticipated by the author. The three
“Categories for Research Proposal” listed in the Research Guidelines
Handbook for BSc/MSc Students & Tutors (2003, 8) issued by the Scottish
School of Herbal Medicine do not directly allude to this method, though
mention is made of case history research. The author suggests that the School
(and other bodies) consider encouraging this method specifically. Initial work
would be required to establish criteria for case series studies.
The second area in which study is
recommended is historical reclamation of theories of practice used in Western
herbalism. The author takes the recent explosion of herbal literature on
Chinese, Ayurvedic, and other forms of herbal medicine as evidence that Western
herbalists are searching for a theory of practice. This is another
observational belief he has picked up while teaching in the herbal community.
In reaching these unanticipated
conclusions, the author acknowledges the influence of Scheid’s (1996) paper on
research design in Chinese medicine. His comments are suggestive of the
unanticipated conclusions reached above. However, note that Scheid (1996)
supports study of single case histories, while the present author is advancing
the use of case series studies consisting of five or more case histories.
The author also concludes that it
would be a good idea for herbalists to incorporate biomedical, visionary, and
analogical methods, as well as paradigmatic research, into Western herbalism.
He believes this would contribute to the maintenance and development of an
effective, broad-minded, holistic profession with a healthy, ‘participatory’
relationship to nature.
11. References
ANGELL, M., and
Kassirer, J. P., 1998. “Alternative medicine – the risks of untested and
unregulated remedies.” New
England Journal of Medicine, Sept. 17; 339 (12):839-841.
BACON, F., 1994. Novum
Organum, With Other Parts of The Great Instauration. First Latin ed., 1620.
Translated and edited by Peter Urbach and John Gibson. Chicago
and La Salle, Illinois: Open
Court.
BENSKY, D., and GAMBLE,
A., 1986. Traditional Chinese Medicine: Materia Medica. Seattle:
Eastland Publishing.
BENSOUSSAN, A., TALLEY,
N. J., HING, M., MENZIES, R., GUSO, A., and NGU, M., 1998. “Treatment of
Irritable Bowel Syndrome with Chinese Herbal Medicine: A Randomized Controlled
Trial.” Journal of the American Medical Association, Nov. 11; 280
(18):1585-9.
BUHNER, S. H., 1996. Sacred
Plant Medicine: Exploration in the Practice of Indigenous Herbalism. Boulder:
Roberts Rinehart Publishers.
–––––––––– . 2005. Healing
Lyme:Natural Healing And Prevention of Lyme Borreliosis And Its Coinfections.
White River Junction, VT: Chelsea Green.
CAJETE, G., 2000. Native
Science: Natural Laws of Interdependence. Santa Fe: Clear Light
Publishers.
CHISHTI, H. G. M.,
1988. The Traditional Healer: A Comprehensive Guide to the Principles and
Practice of Unani Herbal Medicine. Rochester, VT: Healing Arts Press.
CLAGETT, M., 1955. Greek
Science in Antiquity. New York: Abelard-Schuman.
COWAN, E., 1995. Plant
Spirit Medicine. Newberg, OR: Swan•Raven & Co.
CRELLIN, J. K., and
Philpott, J., 1990. Herbal Medicine Past and Present: Volume I, Trying to
Give Ease. Durham and London: Duke University Press.
CULPEPER, N., 1990. “A
Key to Galen’s Method of Physic.” In Culpeper’s Complete Herbal and English
Physician. Glenwood, IL: Meyerbooks.
CUMSTON, C. G., 1987. An
Introduction to the History of Medicine: From the time of the Pharaohs To the
end of the XVIIIth Century. History of Civilization Series. First ed.,
1928. New York: Dorset.
DAVENPORT, G., 1979. Herakleitos and Diogenes. Bolinas,
CA: Grey Fox Press.
DAVIDOFF, F., HAYNES,
B., SACKETT, D., and SMITH, R., 1995. “Evidence-based medicine.” British
Medical Journal, Apr. 29, 310:1085-1086.
DeANGELIS, K., and
FONTANAROSA, P., 2003. “Drugs Alias Dietary Supplements.” Journal of the
American Medical Association, Sept. 17; 290 (11):1519-20.
DORSON, R. M., 1952. Bloodstoppers
and Bearwalkers: Folk Traditions of the Upper Peninsula. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
DUBIK, M., 2004.
“Echinacea Not Found Efficacious for Treatment of URI
Symptoms.” AAP Grand Rounds, Feb., 11(2):17-23.
EAMON, W., 1994. Science
and the Secrets of Nature: Books of Secrets in Medieval and Early Modern
Culture. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
EISENBERG, D. M.,
DAVIS, R. B., ETTNER, S. L., APPEL, S. WILKEY, S., VAN ROMPAY, M., and KESSLER,
R., 1998. “Trends in Alternative Medicine Use in the United States,
1990-1997.” Journal of the American Medical Association, Nov. 11; 280
(18):1569-1575.
ERNST, E., 2002.
“Evidence-Based Herbalism.” In Phytochemicals in Nutrition and Health. MESKIN,
M. S., BIDLACK, W. R., DAVIS, A. J., and OMAYE, S. T., ed. London, New York: CRC
Press.
FLEMING, T., ed., 1998.
PDR for Herbal Medicines. Montvale,
NJ: Medical Economics Company.
FONTANAROSA, P. B.,
RENNIE, D., and DeANGELIS, C. D., 2005. “The need for regulation of dietary
supplements – lessons from ephedra.” Journal of the American Medical
Association, Mar. 26; 289(12):1568-1571.
FRAZIER, J. G., 1990. The
New Golden Bough: A New Abridgment of the Classic Work. First ed.,
1890. Edited, with notes and a new foreword by T. H. Gaster. Garden City, NY:
Anchor Books.
FUGH-BERMAN, A., 1996. Alternative
Medicine: What Works, A Comprehensive, Easy-to-read Review of the Scientifc
Evidence, Pro and Con. Tucson: Odonian Press.
FYFE, J. W., 1909. Specific
Diagnosis and Specific Medication. Cincinnati: Scudder Brothers Company.
GERARD, J., 1975. The
Herbal, or General History of Plants: The Complete 1633 Edition as Revised and
Enlarged by Thomas Johnson. First ed., 1595. New York:
Dover Publications.
GOLDSTEIN, M. S., 1999.
Alternative Health Care: Medicine, Miracle, or Mirage? Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
GOSS, I. J.
M., 1885. The American Practice of Medicine: Including the Diseases of Women
and Children, Based Upon the Pathological Indications of the Remedies Advised.
Second ed. Philadelphia: Samuel M. Miller, M.D., Medical Publisher.
GRIEVE, M., 1994. A
Modern Herbal: The Medicinal, Culinary, Cosmetic and Economic Properties,
Cultivation and Folklore of Herbs, Grasses, Fungi, Shrubs and Trees With All
Their Modern Scientific Uses. First ed., 1931. Edited by C. Leyel. London:
Tiger Books International.
HALL, D. 1988. Creating Your Herbal Profile. New Canaan,
NY: Keats Publishing, Inc.
HALLER, J. S., 1997. Kindly
Medicine: Physio-Medicalism in America, 1828-1911. Kent, OH:
The Kent State University Press.
HAYNES, R. B., 1999.
“Commentary: A warning to complementary medicine practitioners: get empirical
or else.” British Medical Journal, Dec. 18; 319:1633-1634.
HENRY, J., 2002. Knowledge
is Power: How Magic, the Government and an Apocalyptic Vision inspired Francis
Bacon to create Modern Science. Cambridge, UK: Icon Books.
HILL, J., 1789. The
Useful Family-Herbal. First ed., 1740. A New Edition, Corrected. London:
Wilson and Spence.
HIPPOCRATES, 1950. The
Medical Works of Hippocrates: A new translation from the original Greek made
especially for English readers. Translated and edited by Chadwick, J., and
Mann, W. M. Oxford: Blackwell Scientific Publications.
HOFFMANN, D., 2003. Medical
Herbalism: The Science and Practice of Herbal Medicine. Rochester,
VT: Healing Arts Press.
–––––––––– , 1992. The
New Holistic Herbal. First ed., 1983. Shaftesbury, Dorset, and Rockport,
MA: Element, Inc.
HOLMES, P., 1997. The
Energetics of Western Herbs. v. 1. Third ed. Boulder:
Snow Lotus Press.
HORGAN, J., 1997. The
End of Science: Facing the Limits of Knowledge in the Twilight of the
Scientific Age. First ed., 1996. New
York: Broadway Books.
HOUSE OF LORDS SELECT
COMMITTEE ON SCIENCE AND TECHNOLOGY, 2000. 6th Report: Complementary
and Alternative Medicine. London: Stationary Office.
IOANNIDIS, J., 2005.
“Why Most Published Research Findings Are False.” PLOS Medicine, Aug.;
2(8):e124. Available at: http://medicine.plosjournals.org. [Accessed Dec. 31, 2005].
JOUANNA, J., 1999. Hippocrates.
Medicine and Culture Series. Translated by M. B. DeBevoise. Baltimore
and London: The Johns Hopkins University Press.
JUNG, C. G., 1976. Psychological
Types. A revision by R. F. C. Hull, of the translation by H. G. Baynes. Princeton:
Princeton University Press/Bollingen.
KAPTCHUK, T. J., and
EISENBERG, D. M., 1998. “The persuasive appeal of alternative medicine.” Annals
of Internal Medicine. Dec. 15; 129 (12): 1061-1065.
KLOSS, J., 1962. Back
to Eden: A Human Interest Story of Health and
Restoration to be found in Herb, Root and Bark. First ed., 1939. Coalmont, TN: Longview
Publishing House.
KOESTLER, A., 1964. The
Sleepwalkers: History of Man’s Changing Vision of the Universe. Harmondsworth:
Penguin Books, Ltd.
KOLLMAN, C., and
VICKERS, A., 1999. “ABC of complementary medicine; What is complementary medicine?”
British Medical Journal, Sept. 11; 319:693-696.
KOSSO, P., 1992. Reading
the Book of Nature: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Science. Cambridge,
New York: Cambridge University Press.
KUBLER-ROSS,
E., 1994. Questions and Answers on Death and Dying. New York:
Palgrave MacMillan.
KUHN, T. S., 1977. The
Essential Tension: Selected Studies in Scientific Tradition and Change. Chicago
and London: The University of Chicago Press.
–––––––––– , 1970. The
Structure of Scientific Revolutions. First ed., 1962. Second ed., enlarged.
Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press.
LAD, V., and FRAWLEY, D., 1986. The Yoga of
Herbs: an Ayurvedic Guide to Herbal Medicine. Santa Fe:
Lotus Press.
LEIBOVICI, L., 1999.
“Alternative (complementary) medicine: a cuckoo in the nest of empiricist reed
warblers.” British Medical Journal, Dec. 18; 319:1629-1632.
LESASSIER, W., 2001.
Class notes taken by Matthew Wood at Meadows of Dan, VA,
July 1-7.
LINDLAHR, H., 1917. Nature
Cure. Chicago: Nature Cure Publishing Co.
LOWN, B., 1996. The
Art of Healing: Practicing Compassion in Medicine. Boston:
Houghton Mifflin Company.
MEES, L. F. C., 1983. Blessed
by Illness. Spring Valley, NY: Anthroposophic Press.
MENZIES-TRULL, C.,
2003. Herbal Medicine: Keys to Physiomedicalism including Pharmacopoeia. Newcastle,
UK: Published by the Faculty of Physiomedical Herbal Medicine.
MILLS, S., and BONE,
K., 2000. Principles and Practice of Phytotherapy: Modern Herbal Medicine. Edinburgh:
Churchill Livingstone.
MILTON, R., 1994. Alternative
Science: Challenging the Myths of the Scientific Establishment. Rochester,
VT: Park Street Press.
MURE, G. R. G., 1964. Aristotle.
First ed., 1932. New York: Oxford University Press.
NARBY, J., 1998. The
Cosmic Serpent: DNA and the Origins of Knowledge. New York:
Jeremy P. Tarcher/Putnam.
NARBY, J. ed., and
HUXLEY, F., ed., 2004. Shamans Through Time: 500 Years on the Path to
Knowledge. New York: Jeremy P. Tarcher/Penguin.
NEEDLEMAN, J., 2003. A
Sense of the Cosmos: Scientific Knowledge and Spiritual Truth. First ed.,
1976. Rhinebeck, NY: Monkfish Book Publishing Company.
PAGEL, W., 1983. Paracelsus:
An Introduction to Philosophical Medicine in the Era of the Renaissance. Second
revised ed. Basel, Munich, Paris, London, New
York, Tokyo,
Sydney: Karger.
PANOS, M., and
HEIMLICH, J., 1980. Homeopathic Medicine at Home. Los Angeles: J. P. Tarcher, Inc.
PARACELSUS, 1958. Paracelsus:
Selected Writings. Translated and edited by Jolande Jacobi. First ed.,
1952. Second ed. Bollingen Series XXVIII. New
York: Pantheon Books, 1958.
PATTON, D., 2006.
Personal communication.
RED ELK,
P., 2005. Personal communication.
RICKEN, F., 1991. Philosophy
of the Ancients. Translated by E. Watkins. Notre Dame, London:
University of Notre
Dam Press.
RIESE, W., 1953. The
Conception of Disease: its History, its Versions and its Nature. New York:
Philosophical Library.
RITTER, J. M., 1985. Dioscorides
on Pharmacy and Medicine. Austin: University of Texas Press.
ROSNER, F., 1989. The
Medical Aphorisms of Moses Maimonides. Maimonides’ Medical Writings. v. 3. Haifa:
The Maimonides Research Institute.
SACKETT, D. L.,
RICHARDSON, W. S., ROSENBERG, W., and HAYNES, R. B., 1997. Evidence-based
Medicine: How to Practice & Teach EBM. New York, Edinburgh,
London, Madrid, Melbourne, San
Francisco, Tokyo:
Churchill Livingstone.
SALMON, W., 1710. Botanologia,
The English Herbal: or, History of Plants. London: Printed by I.
Dawkes, for H. Rhodes, at the Star, the Corner of Bride-Lane, in Fleet-Street;
and J. Taylor, at the Ship in Pater-noster-Row.
SAMPSON, W., 2005.
“Studying Herbal Remedies.” New
England Journal of
Medicine. July 28; 353:337-339.
SCHEID, V., 1996.
Research(ing) Tradition(s): Comparing Traditional Chinese and Biomedical
Approaches. In: Acupuncture Resource Research Centre (ARRC) Conference Papers,
pp. 9-12.
SCHMIDT, R. 2005.
Personal communication.
SCOTTISH SCHOOL OF HERBAL MEDICINE, 2003. Research Guidelines
Handbook for BSc/MSc Students & Tutors. Class Handout.
SCUDDER, J. M., 1985a. Specific
Diagnosis: A Study of Disease with Special Reference to the Administration of
Remedies. First ed., 1874, reprinted. Portland,
OR: Eclectic Medical Publications.
–––––––––– , 1985b. Specific
Medication and Specific Medicines. First ed., 1870, fourth revision,
fifteenth ed., 1903, reprinted. Portland, OR: Eclectic Medical Publications.
STARFIELD, B., 2000.
“Is US Health Really the Best in the World?” Journal of the American Medical
Association, July 26; 284(4):483-485.
STORL, W. D., 1990. Culture
and Horticulture: A Philosophy of Gardening. San Francisco:
Bio-Dynamic Farming and Gardening Association.
SUDHOFF, K., ed.,
1922-3. Paracelsus Werke. First series. 15 v. Munich:
R. Oldenburg.
THOMSON, S., 1825a.
New Guide to Health: or, Botanic Family Physician, To Which is Prefaced a
Narrative of the Life and Medical Discoveries of the Author. Second ed. Boston:
Printed for the Author, by E. G. House.
–––––––––– , 1825b. New
Guide to Health: or, Botanic Family Physician, Containing a Complete System of
Practice, From a Plan Entirely New. Second ed. Boston:
Printed for the Author, by E. G. House.
THURSTON, J. M., 1900. The
Philosophy of Physio-Medicalism. New Richmond, IN: privately published.
TIERRA, M., 1983. The
Way of Herbs. New York: Washington
Square Press.
TURNER, P., ed. 1992. The
History of the World, Commonly Called the Natural History of C. Plinius
Secondus, or Pliny. From the translation by Philemon Holland, 1601. New York:
Southern Illinois University Press.
TURNER, R. B., BAUER,
R., WOELKART, K., THOMAS, C. H., and GANGEMI, J. D., 2005. “An Evaluation of Echinacea
angustifolia in Experimental Rhinoverus Infections.” New England Journal of Medicine, July
28; 353:341-348.
UNITED STATES
DEPARTMENT OF HEALTH, EDUCATION, AND WELFARE, 2002. The Final Report of the White
House Commission on Complementary and Alternative Medicine. Washington,
D.C.: U. S. Government Printing Office.
VAUGHAN, T., 1968. The
Works of Thomas Vaughan, Mystic & Alchemist. First ed., 1919. A. E. Waite,
ed. New Hyde Park, NY: University Books.
VICKERS, A., 1996.
“Research paradigms in mainstream and complementary medicine.” In: ERNST, E.,
ed. Complementary medicine: an objective appraisal. Oxford:
Butterworth-Heinemann.
WEBB, W. H., 1916. Standard Guide to
Non-Poisonous Herbal Medicine. Southport, UK: “Visitor” Printing Works.
WEED, S., 1989. Wise
Woman Herbal: Healing Wise. Woodstock, NY: Ash Tree Publishing.
WEISS, S., and WEISS,
G., 1992. Growing & Using the Healing Herbs. New York,
and Avenel, NJ: Winged Press.
WHITELEGG, M., 2003.
“Goethean Science: An Alternative Approach.” In, The Journal of
Alternative and Complementary Medicine, Spring, 9(2):311-320.
WOOD, M., 2004. The
Practice of Traditional Western Herbalism. Berkeley, CA: North Atlantic Books.
–––––––––– , 2005. Vitalism:
The History of Herbalism, Homeopathy, and Flower Essences. First ed.,
1992, entitled “The Magical Staff.” Berkeley, CA: North
Atlantic Books.
WYNGAARDEN, J.B., 1985.
“Medicine and Science.” In: WYNGAARDEN, J.B., ed., and SMITH, L.H., ed. Cecil
Textbook of Medicine. Seventeenth ed. Philadelphia, W.B. Saunders Co.
YAHN, G., 1979. “The
impact of holistic medicine, medical groups, and health concepts.” Journal
of the American Medical Association, Nov. 16; 242(20):2202-5.
ZAKAY-RONES, Z.,
VARSANO, N., ZLOTNIK, M., MANOR, O., REGEV, I., SCHLESINGER, M., and
MUMCUOGLU, M., 1995. “Inhibition of several strains of influenza virus in vitro
and reduction of symptoms by an elderberry extract (Sambucus nigra L.) during
an outbreak of influenza B. Panama.” Journal of Alternative and
Complementary Medicine, Winter; 1(4):361-9.